Monday 30 April 2012

Self-Assertion of an English Garden (After-Life Topoi of Nazi Desire) Chapter 6.2.


1.     Il faut cultiver notre jardin   
2.     Pêcheurs de lune
3.     Iterability of the Nazi State (Economy of Genocide)
4.     Growth (and Form/Morphe)
5.     Decay
6.     Pompes Funèbres
6.1.  Type (Model, Example, Tupos)
6.2.  Usus Tyrannus (Interlude)
6.3.  The Ageing of a Note
7.      Critique of Beginnings
8.      Demonology of Defeat 





6.      Pompes Funèbres


6.2.    Usus Tyrannus (Interlude)

The affinity between tyranny and work is ancient.  Fascism and Nazism did not invent it.  The inscription on the portal to Auschwitz “Arbeit macht frei” is the pure expression of this continuity.  The ‘modernism’ of Nazism, how it improves upon the ancient programs of public works, comes from later capitalism.  Work is not only production, it is equally destruction – in Nazi parlance, extermination is “Vernichtung durch Arbeit” (extermination through work).  The worker works, carrying out the work of extermination and exterminating himself at the same time.  The work of extermination is peculiarly reflexive – as the raw material and the worker are identical.  The concept of work itself can never be exterminated.  The whole idea of the Camp is centred on labour.  Hitler, Himmler et al. conceived and designed Auschwitz as the site of slave labour camps supplying the needs of I.G.-Farben for the production of synthetic rubber and other chemical products.  Birkenau, its sibling camp, was the facility for extermination sans phrase, housing crematoria and gas chambers.

The obsession with work arose at the very inception of Nazism.  Till this day Hitler is often excused by citing those “good works” he instigated – building the Autobahn, putting the horde of unemployed to work.  Similarly, high unemployment is traditionally seen as a major ‘cause’ of Nazism.  Haider’s praise of Hitler’s employment policies showed his instinctive awareness that Nazi tyranny thrives on work and not myth.   Although Nazi work itself can create its own mythology – as in Ernst Jünger’s Der Arbeiter (adopted by Heidegger) or the writings of Niekisch and other ‘National Bolshevists’.  A peculiarity of the Nazi mythology of work – the proletariat is not a class but the whole nation-race.  


Hitler came from the unemployed underclass of Vienna, the asylums for homeless and jobless, obviously a good place to conceive mass employment programs for others.  His personal inclinations were untainted by any “work ethic”.  The sybaritic lusts and habits of Hitler and his inner circle could not have contrasted more starkly with the official ideology of what Heidegger emulating Jünger calls the “Work State”.  Neither work nor the state interested Hitler - he saw both only as the means of fashioning his “war machine” for the conquest of world power (measured above all in territory) – always a threat or risk, as Deleuze/Guattari analyze (A Thousand Plateaus) – for state or juridical sovereignty (the apparatus).  All discourse of the “state of exception” (Schmitt, Agamben, Derrida) conflates these two antinomian elements of power; the state is not the end and fulfilment of power nor is sovereignty the unsurpassable zenith of domination.  Sebastian Haffner counts Hitler’s neglect of the state as one of his ‘mistakes’ – he was not a statesman, he destroyed “German state-ness” – created “states in states” – an accusation also voiced by Speer.
Hitler interessierte sich nicht für den Staat, verstand nichts vom Staat and hielt nichts vom Staat.  Nur auf Völker und Rassen kam es ihm an, nicht auf die Staaten.  Der Staat war ihm “nur ein Mittel zum Zweck” und zwar, kurz gesagt, zum Zweck des Kriegführens.  An Kriegsvorbereitung hat es Hitler in den Jahren 1933-1939 nicht fehlen lassen, aber was er schuf, war eine Kriegsmaschine, kein Staat.  Und das sollte sich rächen.” [“Hitler was not interested in the state, understood nothing about the state and did not consider the state to be worth much.  Only people and races counted for him, not states.  The state was “only a means to the end” and that was, in short, the end of waging war.  Hitler did not neglect war preparations in those years 1933-1939, but what he created was a war machine not a state.  And that would take its revenge.” (Sebastian Haffner, Anmerkungen zu Hitler, Frankfurt, 1990, p. 86)]
But without this ‘mistake’ – there would have been neither a Hitler nor the so-called third Reich.  Considering the Nazi position towards Hegel’s concept of state, Marcuse regards their rejection of both the Rechststaat (state of law) and Hegel as a given or almost a truism.  As opposed to the Italian fascists’ espousal of Hegel, the Nazi ideologists deemed Hegel the “counter-will” (Franz Böhm) to their own enterprise, especially his idea of a state based on universal juridical principles and freedom of the conscious individual, not Volkheit.  Carl Schmitt said that the day Hitler ascended to power is the “day Hegel died” – although Schmitt’s own ‘Hegelianism’ and etatism soldiered on regardless.  Heidegger though in an indirect retort contests this claim of his ‘rival’ Schmitt, when he begins the 8th session of the lecture course on “Hegel, On the State” (1934-1935) with the remark – that contrary to what ‘has been said’, Hegel did not die on that day in January 1933, rather he came to life.  All these seeming discrepancies in the Nazi hierarchy’s philosophical position towards Hegel and/or the State – is merely the academic reflection in abstracto of the ambiguity and the peculiar hybridism of the Nazi regime itself.  As Marcuse, writing in 1940, remarks – the new regime in Germany had rather to dismantle a previous massive state bureaucracy (in other words Prussia) to further its aims than to ‘build’ an even stronger one – in Italy fascism was more the ‘means’ to invent such a unified state apparatus.  Paradoxically, Nazism almost shares ‘neo-liberalism’s’ ideal of ‘less state’ or even no state (so-called deregulation) – approximating what Negri and Hardt call ‘Empire’, - although significantly the present day stateless ‘Empire’ of Negri and Hardt remains addicted to the Schmittian idea of sovereign exception for it “to be called into Being”. (See Michael Hardt, Antonio Negri, Empire, Cambridge/London, 2000, pp. 15 ff.)  Similarly, Agamben’s idolization of sovereign power in the sense of the ‘biopolitical’ State is in the tradition of Italian fascism and not Nazism.  The Nazi regime did not rule in the name of Volkheit or only to the extent that it eliminated barriers of the existing political forms hindering the total and direct economic exploitation of all possible human and material resources. 
“In contrast to Italy, the German state had been a powerful and firmly established reality, which even the Weimar Republic had not shaken in its foundations.  It was a Rechtsstaat, a comprehensive rational political system with distinctly demarcated and recognized spheres of rights and liberties that could not be utilized by the new authoritarian regime.  Moreover, the latter could discard the state form because the economic powers who stood behind the National Socialist movement were long since strong enough to govern directly, without the unnecessary mediation of political forms that would have to grant at least a minimum of legal equality and security.” (Herbert Marcuse, Reason and Revolution, London and Henley, 1977, p. 412)  Denuded of the state, Volkheit though enters into a direct bondage (called “lebendige Verbundenheit”: living bond by both Heidegger and Schmitt) far more extreme than to a state of law – in a retrograde imitation of the feudal order of protego ergo obligo (cited by Schmitt in The Concept of the Political as the cogito ergo sum of the state) and of an erotic Minnedienst  – Volkheit kneels before its master and Beloved, the Führer.  Although the Führer is also the Lover, the erâstes, as he is mostly the active male part in the relationship whose word (das Führerwort) Volkheit must instantly obey.  In the vocabulary of ancient Greek pederasty – the Volk is the morbid form of the passive youth khorous or eromenos – one who remains the passive object beyond the time of youth – called kinaidos or the “penetrated one”.

The third Reich was the precise location of the destruction/cannibalisation of the juridical state by the war machine – or interiority by pure exteriority, polis by nomos.  The exterminatory war machine was the non-identical of the conservationist State (the residual sovereignty) – but could never be reconciled with it or subsumed under its aegis.  (Hence calling the Nazi entity totalitarian or a total state is a misnomer.)  In the end the war machine will destroy the state  – the war machine meant to augment power indefinitely will also exterminate its ‘host’ – the State – by drawing down upon itself the exterminatory power of other outer war machines.  The Nazi war-machine is not what Poulantzas calls an “exceptional state” – it is not a state at all.  An indirect proof – the state alias the war machine adopted the nomadic form of the camp – the encampment – from the very beginning in 1933.  First for the indoctrination of human Nazi material in “Work Camps” – Heidegger was particularly engaged in recruiting and indoctrinating students for these labour camps, youth who were to be hardened and made over in the model of Nazi “self-assertion” – work at this time replaces Care (Sorge) in his philosophy as the primary modality of being.  Later the “Lagerwelt” (camp world) was the platform upon which the SS (the inner core of the war machine) sought to erect its eastern empire.  Thus given the Fata Morgana of the Nazi ‘state’ - Heidegger’s panegyric for its Nazi incipience, the new ‘polis’ – the one to be conducted by the new ‘type’ of the worker-student, member of the ‘hard race’, reveal the folie de grandeur of a self-deluding provincial academic, who thinks his chance for ‘real’ power, ‘world power’ has miraculously arrived with Being’s gift of Adolf Hitler.

[Commentary:  Deleuze and Guattari make no mention of Carl Schmitt in A Thousand Plateaus – but use nomos in a way opposite to his nomos of sovereignty or law.  Nomos is the code of the war machine and all such organizations not reducible to any state.  Such an organization can be less or more than a state.  The Internet is also a war machine – according to this analysis.  “What becomes clear is that bands, no less than worldwide organization imply a form irreducible to the State and that this form of exteriority necessarily presents itself as a diffuse and polymorphous war machine.  It is a nomos very different from the “law”.  The State-form as a form of interiority, has a tendency to reproduce itself, remaining identical to itself across its variations and easily recognizable within the limits of its poles, always seeking public recognition (there is no masked State).” (Gilles Deleuze and Félix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, London/New York, 2011, p. 360)

A state doesn’t last like an inanimate object or fabricated thing with finite tangible borders or boundaries.  It repeats itself in time; its principles are rules of repetition, extending its substance (assets) into a temporal quasi-body.  Its ‘longevity’ is its ‘iterability’ – a power body that can be repeated indefinitely - at least hypothetically.  The state (or at least the theories of sovereignty) presuppose the same principle expressed by Spinoza in his Ethics as the essence of every being or thing – suum esse conservare – the self, in this case the self of sovereignty – cannot do anything but preserve itself.  Self-preservation and self (sovereignty) are identical – whether of the singular or the transindividual “grand homme” of the state.

Thus, theories of sovereignty or of the classical state and its legal juridical apparatus cannot grasp the peculiarity of the Nazi entity – because it was not a state – rather a construction or Gestalt designed consciously or unconsciously to last the life of one man (the Führer) – non-repeatable or imitable.  Ironically, Heidegger’s determination of Dasein’s essence to be its own annihilation – Sein zum Tode – in which he appears to contradict Spinoza’s dictum of self-preservation – realized itself most completely in that entity embodying the collective Dasein of the German Volk for which he aspired to indefinite duration – the ‘Nazi state’.  But the ‘Nazi-state’ did not die in Heidegger’s sense of death as Würde (dignity) – as if it were an honour conferred by the state.  It ended like an animal in the decay of ‘suppressed bestiality’ – the symbiosis of Führer and Volk.
A sign of the voluntarist biological nature of the Nazi construction is its striking temporal symmetry – an effect of the ticking of Hitler’s biological clock.  The period during which it existed is almost neatly divided into two halves: 6 years ‘peace’ or preparation for war from 1933-1939 and 6 years war – whereby the end is decided not inside but outside of the entity.  Or if from the inside – only in the sense that the substance of the war machine was only worth 6 years of active war.  Italian fascism has nothing of this symmetry or inner partition – confirming that its authentic or classical ‘state’ parts – those, which were recognizable and repeatable, were greater than in the Nazi entity.]

Foucault seems to have touched on this dilemma or predicament of the state and the anti-state – although he still tries to resolve it within one state structure of power, leading him to rather strained compromises.  He questions a juridical state based on law as the exclusive site of power – but not the frame of the state as such.  Otherwise why would he persist in the question of the fabrication of subjects, euphemistically called subjectivity?  Primarily because Foucault like his followers (Agamben, Esposito, Negri and Hardt) or imitators (Derrida) cannot imagine an exterior to the state or in other words sovereignty – the state in its interiority (whether defined by law or solely by coercive force) constitutes the cosmos of power in its entirety. Subject is a term denoting the form or mode of the subjugation of a singular within and by some sort of sovereign body.  Or as Deleuze/Guattari emphasize:
“The State is what makes the distinction between governors and governed possible.” (ibid., p. 359)

Although Hardt and Negri so emphatically pay their respects to Deleuze/Guattari of Mille Plateaux, they assert with finality that their
Empire, the ‘new’ form of sovereignty, is pure immanence in other words interiority.  There is no escape from this all-inclusive infinite empire unbounded in time and space – far less than from some old-fashioned sovereign state or even a particular empire.  Almost triumphantly the authors assert that although the nation-state is dead – sovereignty is more alive than ever.  The state can disappear (‘wither away’ as Marx once said) – but the holy ghost of sovereignty is forever and everywhere and nameless. 
This so-called new paradigm of global sovereignty – although now swallowing the entire planet – falters in the same way as the old sovereignty – it is unable to conceive of any force outside of itself.  But it is precisely outside of sovereignty that resistance takes place – if at all.

For state-power (or Empire) like being there is never an outside of itself – how could there be when all there is presupposes their givenness, their ‘standing out’.  Hence also the concepts of immunity or autoimmunity refer only (and are limited) to this interiority of the state – analogous to a unified consciousness in Kant and Hume – upon which any accidents or aspects of consciousness (contiguity, causality, succession) utterly depend.  How could one think self-destruction or self-sacrifice if there were no enclosed limited self/state?

Sovereignty is limited to the State or Empire-State – the State is the limit of sovereignty and sovereignty’s “state of exception”.  

But Hardt and Negri at least are caught in a double bind, – somewhere within this insurmountable all-consuming totality of Empire – they posit with equal fervour its nemesis – so-called Multitude.  So despite referring in the obligatory manner to Schmitt’s ‘teaching’ - ‘sovereign is he who decides on the exception’, their euphoric notion of multitude, generation, desire compels the authors to undermine precisely this key concept – “the state of permanent exception” (Hardt and Negri, ibid., p. 17).  “In biopolitical society, for example, fear cannot be employed as Thomas Hobbes proposed, as the exclusive motor of the contractual constitution of politics, thus negating the love of the multitude.  Or rather in the biopolitical society the decision of the sovereign can never negate the desire of the multitude.” (ibid. p. 388)  If that were only true!  Or, as they say, ‘your word in God’s ear’.  This obviously means though that there is a limit to the decision of the sovereign upon the exception – if the multitude’s desires are against the exception, or what amounts to the same thing, against the sovereign and his right/ability to decide upon the exception (like in Egypt of the military junta) – then the status of sovereign (in whatever form) is not absolute.

[Tahrir Square is the earthly site where the ‘desire of the multitude’ confronts the sovereign decision on the exception most concretely and abstractly at this point in the eternal war between ‘Empire’ and ‘Counter-Empire’.  The Egyptian revolutionaries recognize that the ‘permanent state of emergency’ is the sovereign decision on the exception itself.  Hence the most acute revolutionary contradiction occurs now in the ‘2nd phase’ of the Egyptian Revolution of Tahrir Square – where the ‘multitude’ of anti-sovereignty revolutionaries opposes the divine right of sovereign exception anywhere and as such.  This is the logic behind their call for the end of the military rule of ‘SCAF’ (Supreme Command of the Armed Forces) under the so-called state of emergency.  Could one say that if Mubarak was the ‘worst’ – now the military junta is beyond the ‘worst’ – transcending the ‘worst’ means exiting one scale of ‘worst’ and entering a new higher more finely calibrated one – like an ascent in Piranesi’s Carceri?]

The symbiotic connection between sovereign decision and state of emergency is as tautological and circular as any Heideggerian argument about Being and Essence.  The unconscious theoretical ‘desire’ animating Hardt and Negri’s ‘Empire’ is to implement a concept of sovereignty, which having departed its vulnerable state form, its measly larva, becomes finally invincible as a predicate of the perpetual quasi divine ‘Earthly City’.  Their depiction of the new ‘militant’ of this biopolitical order recreates the inverted logic of messianic apostasy – the revolutionary or insurrectionist is the true and positive constituent of the new claustrophobic structure of “Empire” – a (de)formation by definition without an outside or a transcendence and thus impossible to overthrow.  Resistance is subsumed in the act of “constitutive investment in the biopolitical realm” (Hardt and Negri, Empire, ibid. p. 413).  (So for instance the employees of the British department store chain John Lewis who own shares of the company as part of their salary – would be, in the view of Hardt and Negri, both investing in and resisting the biopolitical realm.  If this would qualify as the creative action of the multitude – then the “John Lewis economy” lauded by the British deputy Prime Minister Clegg, as “responsible popular capitalism” is already a form of ‘counter-empire’. Is the “John Lewis economy” already the revolution?  The share-owning employees also share the risk – like in the case of the collapse of Northern Rock where shares became worthless – but will they ever own enough shares to become the ‘boss’?)  With a Sabbatean proselytism the authors conclude their tractate on Empire, the ‘revolution’ affirming the existing order (‘resistance as investment’):  “Here is the strong novelty of militancy today: it repeats the virtues of insurrectional action of two hundred years of subversive experience, but at the same time it is linked to a new world, a world that knows no outside.  It knows only an inside, a vital and ineluctable participation in the set of social structures, with no possibility of transcending them.” (ibid.)  Dialectic of standstill?  Or are Empire and Counter-Empire (Multitude) figments of a new biopolitical identity philosophy?  Hardt and Negri’s concept of militancy closely resembles the positive constituent acts (work-knowledge-armed service to the Volk) of the biopolitical/racial Nazi entity promulgated by Heidegger as the “self-assertion of the Germany University”.  Similarly, their emphasis on the “lightness and joy” of this indenture to “mass intellectuality” and “cooperative apparatuses of production and community” has the imperious ring of the Nazi slogan of compulsory “Kraft durch Freude” (power through joy) in building the Nazi future/destiny. 
An old-fashioned straightforward membership in the Communist Party would be pure autonomous luxury in comparison with the militant life of poverty in service of the multitude Hardt and Negri propose in imitation of St Francis of Assisi.  One is justified in suspecting as does Benjamin Noys, that in this prospect of a new militancy “(…) a theological discourse (is) at work in which the misery of life is transformed into the glory of Life, in a ‘postmodern passion’ (Negri) that repeats a Christological dialectic.” (Benjamin Noys, “Live Life to the Full”, at No Useless Leniency, 24th March 2012, online)
Not to forget – that St Francis’ carefree and barefoot life amongst the beggars metamorphosed into the Franciscan Order - one of the pillars of the Catholic Church, another model of Empire.  The vision of subservience broadcast by St Francis was one of perfect obedience to one’s superior (perfecta et summa obedientia) – so perfect in its absence/negation of will as to be likened to that of a corpse (corpus mortuum, corpus exanime).

It is a well-known venerable monastic attitude – to find joy in self-annihilation – how though does this translate into the “irrepressible and lightness of joy of being communist” (Hardt and Negri, ibid.)?  One longs for the innocent days of “Euro-communism” (when East was East and West was West).

[Sameness:  The quasi-ecclesiastical obedience of the corpse belongs to the rituals of sadomasochistic ‘slavery’ as much as the leather bars, leather corsets and latex hoods.  Similar to the monk’s perfect obedience to his superior (ultimately to the Pope) – the young men training in the ‘discipline’ of becoming a total object (slave) for a rich master must relinquish control of their bodies.  They forfeit own desire, become ‘as if’ a dead body (corpus mortuum) in the pursuit of transcendent sexual pain-pleasure.  Their lust breeds a spectacle of leisure, which has all the hardship of forced labour.  Not surprisingly, the comparison of sadomasochistic scenes of ‘martyrdom’ and the baroque iconography of Christian sainthood is almost a cliché of homosexual writing (all of Genet, for instance, Notre Dame des Fleurs, Miracle de la Rose, Pompes Funèbres, etc).
As Adrian Rifkin notes: “(…) (Mattia) Preti made better sense of John Preston and the body of the slave, his Saint Sebastian (Capodimente) and Peter in the Desert (Toronto) with their uplifted chins prefiguring the sexual time of waiting for an event in the phantasm of sexual object hood; the slave to an indifferent and disinterested passion (such as that for martyrdom), for a pure idea of sexuality that can properly be seen to extend Sade into an exploration of the relation between individual lust and polymorphous form of desire in contemporary gay mores. (…) And so baroque religion emerges ever more clearly as a possible pathos formel of queer studies (…)” (See Adrian Rifkin, “Slavery”, at Gai-Savoir.net)  “Gay mores” are also a model for Agamben’s ‘sexual bare life’ – as he deduces the “growing importance of sadomasochism in modernity” from its “technique”.  Referring to its lineage from de Sade, especially his 120 Days of Sodom, Agamben writes: “Sadomasochism is precisely the technique of sexuality by which the bare life of a sexual partner is brought to light.  Not only does Sade consciously invoke the analogy with sovereign power (…) but we also find there the symmetry between homo sacer and sovereign, in the complicity that ties the masochist to the sadist, the victim to the executioner.” (Homo Sacer, ibid., pp. 134-135)  Sade is our contemporary, says Agamben, because of his theatrical presentation of sexuality and physiological life as being immediately “biopolitical”.  Was he perhaps thinking less of Sade and more of the Sadiconazista?

The singular monk is also a will-less homo sacer (corpus mortuum) in relation to the sovereign power of the Church or Pope.  Total subservience presented in the monastic order is itself a form of political theatre (theatrum politicum).  But also the sheer vision of the creator God – as a consuming and fertilising essence – a vegetative supremacy, is enough to give rise to monastic onanism and pederasty.

Ignoring for the moment, that Freud sees masochism within the ‘economy of masochism’ as itself a primary drive and not just derived from sadism, before de Sade and the eponymous sadomasochism though was Platonic ‘ontotheology’ ‘worshipped’ by acts of pederasty and homosexuality.  Paul reinterprets Platonic ontotheology, constructing the Christian sacred Trinity around the “homosexual Jesus”.  Pure Identity in the Trinity is God loving Himself and giving Himself a Son – divine hermaphroditism. “Homosexualität ist Liebe zu Gott, zu Jesus – dem fleischgewordenen Logos -, das heisst mönchisches Leben; reine Lust ist Askese.  Durch diese aufs abstrakte Jenseits gerichtete und umfunktionierte Sexualität schlägt in Europa alles Erotische ins Neurotische um (verklemmte Homosexualität).”(“Homosexuality is love of God, of Jesus – the Logos turned flesh - , that means monastic life; pure lust is asceticism.  Through this sexuality, projected and reconstructed/redirected towards an abstract hereafter, everything erotic in Europe turns into the neurotic (repressed homosexuality).”
(“Ontologie und Eros” in Hans-Jürgen Krahl, Konstitution und Klassenkampf, Frankfurt, 1971, p.117)
Pure Identity, the identity of thinking with itself in the Idea, the only true and eternal existence (Sein) is grounded in the homosexual love of the same. The “nervous defect” noted by Proust would be according to Krahl’s genealogy of European homosexuality – a reflex of the Paulinian transformation of the Platonic embedding/sublating of pederasty in the Idea (and the Idea in pederasty?).

Sameness is not a point of origin – rather the reflex or compulsive ingestive act of this totality is to eliminate all differences – and to result in a passive show of sameness.  Sameness is a relation of identity, which ‘comes true’ in the Hegelian sense of a “speculative proposition”.  It is not but will be.
This precisely is how Badiou derives “humanity” from the “anti-humanism of the same”: “Philosophically named, an emancipatory politics, comes within an anti-humanism of the same.  And it is from this anti-humanism, through which the same is supported only by the void of all differences in which to ground Man, that humanity issues.  Humanity, prior to the real forms of egalitarian politics, simply does not exist, either as a collective, or as a truth, or as thought.
It is of this absolute same, that is prior to every idea of humanity, and out of which humanity issues: politics deals with the coming to light of the collective as truth of the same. (…) as the Parmenides translated by Beaufret said, ‘the Same, is at once to think and to be’.” (Alain Badiou, “Philosophy and Politics” in Conditions, ibid., pp. 175-176)  (For Agamben – this “truth of the same” is also the ‘sexual bare life’ “brought to light” by the homosexual sadomasochist technique, itself immediately biopolitical.)

Sameness is teleology of being not its Ur-form.  Or rather it is the idea of sameness mirrored imperfectly in the empirical world.  Same though does not necessarily mean equal or egalitarian.  Amongst the same or the ontology of the same there can still be a difference of hierarchy (as in the succession of ordinal numbers) – in Plato’s homosexual ontology the hierarchy of youth and man was parallel to their sexual ranks: the lower one occupies the feminine position of being sodomized and the higher one, the masculine part, does the sodomizing. Equivalent to pupil and master – although the sameness will increase with time as the pupil acquires some of the mastery of the master. Similarly Heidegger speaks of the One, the few and the many – the hierarchy of the Führer state. 

Still though for Christian asceticism (self-flagellation etc) to revert to homosexual lust and physical (not sublimated) sadomasochistic technique (the fusion of the Greek and the Christian), an absolute decrease in desire must have occurred. The Tough Guy, the archetypical film idol, as Adorno describes him in Minima Moralia, radiates concentrated distaste, nothing can arouse him, moulded into in his leather club chair, his jaded palate turns him unavoidably into an ascetic – instead of flagellations he must punish himself with whiskey and cigar smoke, the only satisfaction is his pride in having drilled his organism to be inured to such stimuli, this fakir regime of self-abnegation is the only pleasure allowed.  He is a sexual ‘hunger artist’, never having found the right food to arouse his appetite.  The Tough Guy is actually a masochist – and his distaste especially for women is his repressed homosexuality, the only acceptable form of the heterosexual. The Tough Guys are only one half of the species – the others are the intellectuals, the effeminate males – Adorno cites Oxford student life as a source for this classification.  The Tough Guy is returned to his origins – in the school of philosophy.  What Krahl calls ontology – Adorno refers to as totality.  Totality is another name for Pure Identity (the Same), the Platonic Idea – as a synonym for the ambient of homosexuality.  The two types – the strong man and the obedient youth (master and slave) – are the extreme poles of the ruling class “on the way into dictatorship”.  A recent example of this couple is the late Austrian Jörg Haider and his circle of political-homosexual ephebes or élèves – it is after a meeting with one of them in the bar, that he crashed at high speed on an empty motorway on his way home.
Am Ende sind die tough guys die eigentlich Effeminierten, die der Weichlinge als ihrer Opfer bedürfen, um nicht zuzugestehen, daß sie ihnen gleichen.  Totalität und Homosexualität gehören zusammen.  Während das Subjekt zugrunde geht, negiert es alles, was nicht seiner eigenen Art ist.” (“In the end the tough guys are the real effeminates, who require the weaklings as their victims, so as not to admit that they are like them.  Totality and homosexuality belong together.  While the subject falls apart, it negates everything which is not of its own kind.”, Theodor W. Adorno, “Tough Baby” in Minima Moralia, Frankfurt, 1980, p.52)

The genealogies of dictatorship and ontology both manifest the unfolding of the Idea of Sameness, physically/physiologically rooted in a transcendent homosexuality. This sameness is constructed out of the negation of the subject.  The relic/vestige of the homosexual subject paradoxically subsists in the condition of “total passivity”, the universal Feminine.  Power in the absence of lust is an act of contraction not expansion as in a Nietzschean sense of Wille zur Macht.  The will to power “on the way into dictatorship” is not the magnification of desire, it is an absolute decrease.  The subject who has lost his appetite finds his unhappy quasi-happiness in the unity of sameness of the dictatorship:  The “count-as-one” multiplicity is the collective monad, which as a whole has nothing to lose.  Everything has been lost in advance individually, so that the collective act of losing and its quantity of destruction appears as negative profit.  In this sense Adorno notes about the German horrors of the thirties and forties: “Nach den Berichten der Zeugen ward lustlos gefoltert, lustlos gemordet und darum vielleicht gerade so über alles Maß hinaus.” (“According to the reports of witnesses, they tortured without lust, they murdered without lust and perhaps therefore beyond all measure.”, Theodor W. Adorno, “Unmaß für Unmaß” in Minima Moralia, ibid. p.131)

The acts of cruelty “without measure” is the only as-if quality, (when quantity reverts to quality), remaining in a universe of unequal sameness where everything is absolutely measurable, a pure world of power (truth) and quantity.
Is this dialectic of Sameness and its “theatre of cruelty” at the heart of Badiou’s category of the generic and of the truth procedures of the “subtractive” ontology?  And are not two of his essential conditions of philosophy – politics and love – mired in the inextricable complicity of “homosexuality and totality”, the order which “most purely asserts the male principle of domination” (Adorno, “Tough Baby”, ibid.)?] 

But what ever happened to ‘The Enemy’ in that folie à deux of absolute Empire and Sovereign Power?  The Enemy is the Absolute Other.   The Enemy is most indispensable for Carl Schmitt, contemporary theory’s archangel of ‘the political’.  Without the Enemy ‘the political’ ceases to exist.  This is a dilemma for the homosexual ‘biopolitical’ dictatorship/totality (of the same) and its theory. 
To use a trite example – the Enemy is under the radar in biopolitics and in Badiou’s philosophy of the Same.  Humanity may not exist but the Enemy does. 

How could there be immunity from the enemy?  Such is the non-logic of Foucault’s claim – the Nazi state is a suicidal state, because Hitler issued orders in April 1945 to destroy the living conditions of the Germans.  (Foucault could have equally called Vichy France a suicidal state because the Vichy Admiralty ordered the scuttling of the French fleet at Toulon.)
Foucault obviously regards all these last minute moves as solely interior to the Führerstaat – not in the context of the death sentence already imposed upon it from the outside of this state.
For proof of this claim he invokes like Esposito who most likely has it from him – reference to a certain telegram-order mentioned in Speer’s Memoirs – the interior speaking to the interior.

Such ‘proof’ of the ‘autoimmunity of the Nazi state’ (Esposito) brings to mind an anecdote told by Montaigne about Julius Caesar who, when asked by a decrepit old Roman soldier for permission to take his own life, replied: “So you think you are still alive?”.  Besides Hitler’s orders were actively ignored or thwarted by other power factions or ‘states’ inside the collapsing Third Reich around Speer and the industry and parts of the army very concerned with their fate in a post-defeat (post-Hitler) Germany.  Even Himmler was convinced he would have a role in the post-Hitler Europe – he told Speer during an audience in his hospital room 40 kilometres outside of Berlin at the end of April 1945: ““Ohne mich kommt Europa auch in Zukunft nicht aus. (…) Es braucht mich weiter als Polizeiminister, um Ruhe zu halten.  Eine Stunde mit Eisenhower und er wird der gleichen Überzeugung sein!  Sie werden bald erkennen, daß sie auf mich angewiesen sind – oder sie bekommen ein heilloses Durcheinander.”” [
“Europe won’t be able to manage without me in the future either. (…) It needs me further as police minister, to keep things quiet.  An hour with Eisenhower and he will be convinced of the same.  They will soon recognize, that they have to rely on me – or they will have a hopeless mess.”(Albert Speer, Erinnerungen, ibid., p. 489)]   Himmler was already negotiating with the Swedish Count Bernadotte about the surrender of the concentration camps to the International Red Cross.  Speer seems to betray a trace of regret and bitterness at the sheer scale of the fall of his Nazi idols, beliefs and loyalties in the midst of total collapse when he comments about Himmler’s ‘turn’: “Früher hatten sie immer davon gesprochen, vor einem Ende alle politischen Häftlinge zu liquidieren.  Jetzt suchte Himmler auf eigene Faust sein Arrangement mit dem Sieger.” (“In the early days they had always said, before an end, all the political prisoners would be liquidated.  Now Himmler was trying on his own behalf to make arrangements with the victor.”, ibid., p. 489)  
One wonders how real Speer’s own nighttime  “decision” was, in February 1945, to “get rid of Hitler”. (see ibid., p. 437)   

The army (Wehrmacht) as a relic of the old Prussian state system had always had a certain ambivalence towards Hitler and his ‘SS-State’ – at least its members presented themselves as such later. The generals Brauchitsch and Halder allegedly ‘considered’ overthrowing Hitler as early as 1939 – they were against the date fixed by Hitler for the invasion of France, because they thought the invasion was doomed to fail.  The Army General Staff felt encroached upon in their exclusive right to govern the German State’s military fortunes – but Brauchitsch, promoted to Generalfeldmarschall, later conducted the Blitzkrieg against France – postponed until 1940.

Speer himself officially opposed and unofficially undermined not only any plans for destruction of the German infrastructure but also the attempt by SA remnants in the Party to ‘incompetently’ take over the economy and defence as the end drew closer. But as Speer documents in exhaustive detail - whatever final orders Hitler issued – starting from the Allied invasion of the Normandy in 1944 if not earlier Hitler was chaotically and inconsistently attempting to apply the age old military tactic of “burnt earth” as part of what in Nazi terms was called “total resistance” – always with the belief that the war would still be won.  He also contemplated destroying large parts of the French industrial plant, but was somehow persuaded not to by Speer under considerations of their possible reconquest.  (Apropos, the Vichy Navy really did scuttle its fleet at Toulon on 27th November 1942, successfully obstructing its capture by Rommel’s “Ghost Division” and the Waffen-SS 2nd SS Panzer Division Das Reich during “Operation Lila”.)

The direct physical annihilation of Germans was never the content/subject of Hitler’s orders, only the destruction of infrastructure, administrative and banking records, or forced evacuations – after or anticipating the breach in the front made by the enemy.  Even a month before the end, shortly after Hitler’s last orders for Germany to self-destruct, he pleaded with Speer to at least say that he still hoped they could or would win the war.  It was Hitler’s “ultimatum” for Speer – if he would give Hitler the verbal assurances of his belief in the Nazi victory, Hitler would retract his destruction orders.  Speer could not oblige Hitler regarding the outcome of the war – but he revived his erotic bonds enough to soften Hitler’s rage. (See Albert Speer, “Hitler’s Ultimatum” in Erinnerungen, ibid.)
As it is Hitler wavered many times in the degree of severity of these orders: destruction was trimmed down to inducing temporary disorder (Lähmung), he gave other contradictory orders to step up the production of tanks and fighter planes for which neither materials nor fuel existed, and otherwise stalled in the same manner as all those further down the chain of command.  No major German installation, coalmine or bridge was ever destroyed by German hand, let alone the transportation or communication networks.  Local commanders and Gauleiter refused Hitler’s orders for forced evacuations of civilians on military and hygienic grounds.  The melodramatic trappings of ‘l’état suicidaire’ were quasi-real elements of a homoerotic end-poker or rather Russian roulette played out between Hitler and his closest associates (Speer, Himmler, Göring etc) in their attitude of final desperation.  The stakes were always either loyalty or treason.

Foucault and Esposito demonstrate with their reference to Hitler’s alleged instructions as ‘proof’ of the suicidal nature of the ‘Nazi state’, that they implicitly identify this ‘state’ absolutely with the personal career and fortunes of Hitler – in other words not a state at all.  They are still fooled by Hitler’s superimposition of his ‘lifetime on worldtime’ – so that the suicide of Hitler, which took place, is ‘proof’ of the suicide of the Nazi people and their state which did not.  Hitler’s ‘last will and testament’ and his suicide are clearly the acts of a man whose own world has ended.  He was a “wreck, a bundle of nerves” an “old man” who trembled with fear when the explosions caused his living crypt of thick layers of concrete and earth to sway down below under the Berlin sand. Once his sartorial delight – the impeccable uniform – was decorated
with leftovers from his meals. (Speer, ibid., p. 474)  Regarding the two bodies of the king – it became brutally clear, that there had only ever been one; world time disappeared into lifetime.  Hitler finishes almost like Emil Jannings in Murnau’s Der letzte Mann (1924) – the once proud liveried doorman of a grand hotel who ends his career as the attendant in the men’s lavatory – reigning over a kingdom of cubicles and pisssoirs.
As Speer observes of Hitler in his final ‘death nest’: “Die Flucht in das zukünftige Todesgewölbe hatte, so schien mir immer, auch symbolische Bedeutung. (...) Wenn er vom Ende sprach, dann von dem seinen und nicht von dem des Volks.  Er hatte die letzte Station seiner Flucht vor der Wirklichkeit erreicht, (...)” [“The flight in the future death vault had also, as it always seemed to me, a symbolic meaning. (…) When he spoke of the end, it was his end and not that of the people.  He had reached the last station of his flight from reality, (…)”, ibid.]
Of his most intimate associates, the Goebbels couple were among the very few of his entourage in the Führerbunker to imitate his suicide.  In a letter to a son by a previous marriage, Mrs Goebbels explained her great joy to be able to follow the Führer in death.  They did not want to be alive in a world in which Nazism was dead.  Mrs Goebbels poisoned her 6 offspring with the help of the resident SS euthanasia doctor, before she and Goebbels shot themselves in the garden of the Reichskanzlei.
Hitler’s only consolation as he told his adjutant Nicolaus von Below after the collapse of the Ardennes offensive is that when “we go”, “we” will take a world (not just the German people) with us.  “Wir kapitulieren nicht, niemals.  Wir können untergehen.  Aber wir werden eine Welt mitnehmen.”[We will never capitulate, never.  We can perish.  But we will take a world with us.   (Nicolaus von Below, Als Hitlers Adjutant 1937-45, Mainz 1980, p. 398 quoted in Eckhard Nordhofen, Eschatologische Gewaltenteilung, Text und Zeit, online)] Hitler’s shrill bravado is both a tautology and an amphiboly – obviously when the enemy pushed Hitler and Nazism into the abyss, their Nazi world went with them – not the world of the victors.  Speer, ever observant of Hitler’s mood changes – describes another ‘end-Hitler’ from his last visit to the bunker.  Hitler spoke to him of his imminent death arrangements: “Ich werde nicht kämpfen.  Die Gefahr ist zu groß, daß ich nur verwundet werde und lebend in die Hände der Russen falle.  Ich möchte auch nicht haben, daß meine Feinde mit meinem Körper Schindluder treiben.  Ich habe angeordnet, daß ich verbrannt werde.  Fräulein Braun will mit mir aus dem Leben gehen und Blondi werde ich vorher erschießen.  Glauben Sie mir, Speer, es fällt mir leicht, mein Leben zu beenden.  Ein kurzer Moment, und ich bin von allem befreit, von diesem qualvollen Dasein erlöst.” [“I am not going to fight.  The danger is too great, that I’ll only be wounded and will fall into the hands of the Russians alive.  I also don’t want my enemies messing around with my body.  I have ordered, that I will be burned.  Fräulein Braun wants to go with me out of life and before that I shall shoot Blondi.  Believe me Speer, it is easy for me to end my life.  One brief moment, and I am liberated from everything, I am released from this torturous Dasein.” (Speer, ibid., p. 483)]


[Commentary:  Speer mentions an interesting detail of his automobile trip to Berlin for that farewell visit to Hitler – he notices that the Autobahn from Berlin in the direction of Hamburg is extraordinarily stuffed with all kinds of vehicles on their way out of Berlin.  They create a supernatural traffic jam.  He wonders how they all have so much petrol and speculates that this must have been that special reserve hoarded up for just this occasion.  Certainly such foresight shows a population with strong instincts of self-preservation.]   

The biopolitical concept of autoimmunity of the Nazi state (Esposito) contends it was an organism, which destroyed itself by a totally interior process of autotoxification.  Autoimmunity, in Esposito’s theory, implies a state of rightness or health, which then succumbs to its own powers of auto-destruction – the Nazi state, will have had to have been normal for it then to have moved/degenerated into an autoimmune abnormality.  Normal in this case would have been the ‘healthy’ bio-political sovereign Nazi bloc.
The description of the Nazi state as a ‘suicide state’ (Foucault) claims that it destroyed itself as a conscious act of sovereign will.

Both interpretations discount and deny the historical extirpation of this quasi-state by the enemy outside of it.

One might ask the simple question – would Hitler have issued any sort of ‘Nero’ orders, or killed himself and his dog had the ‘Russians’ not have driven him into that particular corner under the earth – had the Nazi Reich won their utopian “Endsieg”? 

Even at the point where life approached absolute zero on the Kelvin scale – at Auschwitz – when the Lager died from one moment to the next and the Germans were no longer in the towers – Primo Levi, during the last ten days before the Russians arrived in January 1945, could observe: “(…) something great and new was about to happen; we could finally feel a force around us which was not of Germany; we could concretely feel the impending collapse of that hated world of ours. (…) The Lager, hardly dead, had already begun to decompose.  No more water, or electricity, broken windows and doors slamming in the wind, loose iron-sheet from the roofs screeching, ashes from the fire drifting high, afar.” (Primo Levi, If this is a Man · The Truce, Abacus, 1987, pp. 161-164)

Although Foucault begins his lecture course “Society must be Defended” with an emphatic/resounding farewell to the notion of sovereignty as the exclusive source of power, when he comes to treat of the Nazi ‘State’ he returns to the full blown ‘theory of sovereignty’ he had just been in the process of abandoning.  So that the three principles of sovereignty discarded as insufficient for the analysis of power – “subject, unitary power and law” (“Society must be Defended”, ibid., pp. 43-44) – are dragged out of their coffins again to bolster up Foucault’s idealization of what he sees as the bio-political absolute state. 
“We have, then in Nazi society something that is really quite extraordinary: this is a society which has generalized biopower in an absolute sense, but which has also generalized the sovereign right to kill. (…) There was, in Nazism, a coincidence between a generalized biopower and a dictatorship that was at once absolute and retransmitted throughout the entire social body by this fantastic extension of the right to kill and of exposure to death.  We have an absolutely racist State, an absolutely murderous State, and an absolutely suicidal State.  A racist State, a murderous State and a suicidal State.  The three were necessarily superimposed, and the result was of course both the “final solution” (…) of the years 1942-1943, and then Telegram 71, in which in April 1945, Hitler gave the order to destroy the German people’s own living conditions. (…) That is where this mechanism inscribed in the workings of the modern State leads.  Of course, Nazism alone took the play between the sovereign right to kill and the mechanisms of biopower   to this paroxysmal point.  But this play is in fact inscribed in the workings of all States.” (“Society must be Defended”, ibid. p. 260)  


Fixated as he is on a principle of sovereignty, Foucault does not notice how this so-called generalizing of the sovereign right to kill negates and cancels precisely his postulated absolute sovereignty of the Nazi dictatorship.  So much is true – the power over life and death, traditionally regarded as an exclusive sovereign right – is no longer the monopoly of the sovereign in the Nazi entity.  This dissolving of the monopoly of sovereign violence is just another way of saying that sovereignty in its traditional form is itself dissolved.  So that – “This power to kill, which ran through the entire social body of Nazi society, was first manifested when the power to take life, the power of life and death, was granted not only to the State but to a whole series of individuals, to a considerable number of people (such as the SA, the SS, and so on).  Ultimately, everyone in the Nazi State had the power of life and death over his or her neighbors, if only because of the practice of informing, which effectively meant doing away with the people next door, or having them done away with.” (Foucault, ibid., p. 259)  

Similarly, there is absolutely no ‘necessary superimposition’ of the “fantastic extension of the right to kill” upon an absolute exposure of the German population to death.  How is this logically conclusive?  If a population has acquired greater powers over life and death – of a fantastic nature – why are they therefore more exposed to death?  In keeping with Foucault’s tenets of nascent bio-power – they would rather be less exposed to death to the degree that they are free to murder/kill/expel those others whom they consider to be endangering their own species-livelihood.  They have the right to exercise their own pragmatic eugenics and social Darwinism – and as an added gain confiscate the property of the exterminees.  Or is he suggesting their right to kill itself exposes them to the risk of imminent death from their own kind, hence implicitly re-inventing the rationale of a Hobbesian Leviathan – the need of a salutary power meant to end the bellum omnium contra omnes?
Foucault’s false nexus between a real generalizing of the right to kill in Nazi society and the so-called greater exposure to death of the German mass (‘hardening of the race’) leads him directly to his fallacy of the “absolutely suicidal State”.
 
One wonders how it is possible for Foucault, who defines himself as a diligent historical researcher, to compare the fact of the “final solution” (which did not stop in 1943, but went on till the last gasping breath of the Hitler world in 1945) with mere orders to carry out a so-called ‘suicide’ of the state and its people that were never obeyed or only ‘as if’. On the contrary, German resentment till this day of the Allied bombing campaign and their national obsession of the ‘Vertriebene’ (‘the Expelled’, Germans of East Prussia and other Eastern European countries fleeing the advancing Soviet army) show there was (and is) no inherent suicidal drive in the population.  The majority of the population - from the rich peasants of Westphalia to the zealots of Hitler’s inner following (Gefolgschaft), such as Gauleiter and SS, believed until the final moment that the Führer could never lose, that he was luring the enemy in so close, into his trap so as to bring about the big turning point and the final victory with the “Wunderwaffe” (the wonder weapon).  For them he was still the ‘wolf’ – the belief in his miracle to come, the legendary “Wunderwaffe”, that even the most sober Nazi clung to till the end – was perhaps a relic of the ancient cult of the thaumaturgical kings.

[Commentary:  Apparently even after Hitler and Goebbels ceased proclaiming the imminent deployment of the “wonder weapon” – the rumours spread even more wildly, especially through the horoscope pages of the newspapers.  The German people believed the astrological predictions more than the main news – although the propaganda ministry manipulated them in equal measure.  Goebbels also charged Schwarz van Berk with the circulation of unofficial rumours leaked directly from the internal meetings of Speer’s armament conferences (Rüstungstagungen) – something Speer found out quite late, during the Nuremberg Trials.  “Tatsächlich stellte Goebbels (…) die Meldungen über neue Waffen ein.  Sonderbarerweise aber verstärkten sich die Gerüchte.  Erst im Nürnberger Prozeß erfuhr ich von Fritzsche, einem der ersten Mitarbeiter des Propagandaministers, daß Goebbels ein Spezialressort zur Verbreitung dieser Gerüchte unter Schwarz van Berk eingerichtet hatte.  Nun war mir auch klar, warum diese Gerüchte der Zukunftsentwicklung so nahekamen.  Wie oft saßen wir bei unseren Rüstungstagungen abends zusammen und malten uns die neuen Entwicklungen der Technik aus; auch die Möglichkeiten einer Atombombe wurden dabei erörtert.  Schwarz van Berk aber hatte als Berichterstatter an diesen Tagungen oft teilgenommen und war auch bei den abendlichen Zusammenkünften dabei gewesen.”  (“In fact Goebbels suspended reports about the new weapons.  Strangely, the rumours grew stronger.  It was first in the Nuremberg Trial that I found out from Fritzsche, one of the top collaborators of the propaganda minister, that Goebbels had established a special department for the dissemination of these rumours under Schwarz van Berk.  Now it was clear to me why these rumours came so close to the future developments.  How often did we sit together in the evening at our armament conferences and pictured to ourselves the new developments of technology; also the possibilities of an atom bomb were mentioned on these occasions.  Schwarz van Berk had often taken part in these conferences as a reporter and was also present at the evening gatherings.” Speer, Erinnerungen, ibid., p. 418)
Speer’s claim that he had belated knowledge of the role of van Berk is not quite credible – as he sent a letter in December 1944 to van Berk retracting the invitation to attend these armament conferences after van Berk used sensitive information – “for the second time” - in his article published 10th December 1944 in the magazine Das Reich. (Speer, ibid. p. 579)  In the matter of the “wonder weapon” Speer seems a divided soul – especially considering he had been in charge of its realisation and its failure to materialize.] 


Whatever vindictive orders Hitler issued from his hiding place, the Führerbunker deep in the ground underneath the Reichskanzlei in Berlin, they were little more than an impotent hysterical response to the ongoing relentless annihilation of the Nazi entity by the Red Army and the Allied Forces.  Eyewitnesses described his condition at that time as a “cake gorging ruin” (See Joachim Fest, Der Untergang, Fest Verlag, 2002, p. 135).  Still as late as the 27th of April, 3 days before Hitler’s suicide, a sliver of a propaganda-rumour that the long awaited saviour, Generalleutnant Wenck and his ‘army’ had been sighted in a suburb of Berlin could reawaken in Hitler and his Bunker-companions old euphoric visions of the Russians being bled to death in Berlin (‘Ausbluten der Russen’) and of ‘Endsieg’ (total victory).
[The so-called “Nero-Order” of March 19th 1945 expressed Hitler’s desire to turn Germany into a “Zivilisationswüste” (civilisation desert).  If he issued another such order in April – it would seem that the desert had not yet materialized.  In fact, between 18th March and 7th April 1945 Hitler issued twelve different contradictory orders regarding ‘destruction’.] 


But Foucault’s  fascination with the Nazi anomaly, the so-called ‘état suicidaire’, leads him to other theoretical contortions.
By way of a detour through the “paroxysmal” and the “extraordinary” of the Nazi regime – Foucault regresses in his own methodological considerations to a point prior to his dismantling of sovereignty as a privileged category for the analysis of power.  He absolutizes the Nazi state where the sovereign right to kill has been generalized – clouding his better judgement or avowed principles of the analysis of states in general.  So that the Nazi State – its alleged absolute sovereignty – becomes the model for a restored sovereignty of all States.  Foucault’s corresponding analysis of Nazi ‘biopower’ must naturally once again presuppose a state monopoly of power - although the Nazi State and the German mass/population coincide so as to become one in the generalized sovereign right to kill.  He must also forego his ‘new’ ‘Clausewitzian’ perspective of a society/state in perpetual war with itself.  Esposito echoes these sentiments in the context of his idea of “immunity”: “Nazism works within that logic (immunitary) in such a paroxysmal manner as to turn the protective apparatus against its own body, which is precisely what happens in autoimmune disease.  The final orders of self-destruction put forward by Hitler barricaded in his Berlin bunker offer overwhelming proof.” (Bíos, ibid., p. 10)


[Commentary: Esposito repeatedly invokes “Telegram 71” as the sole historical evidence he needs to ‘prove’ his theory of Nazi autoimmunity. (see ibid. p. 116)  It seems to matter little to him for the “overwhelming proof” of this contention that the “self-destruction” of German living conditions never took place.
His comparison of autoimmune disease and Nazism’s demise is merely a rewarming of the hackneyed analogy of the state as a social body – it is certainly not drawn from any immanent ‘biopolitical specificity’.  In this analogy Esposito reveals the strains in his imposition of a biologistic form on an aggregate of administrative, military and economic (including negative value/reproduction) decisions or orders – in this case orders which were not obeyed.  The word of the Führer had ceased to be law in the case of “destruction”.]    


Most revealingly, Badiou chooses his meditation on Heidegger in Being and Event to ponder upon the multiplicity of nature and its intimate determination of the ‘normal’.  Starting with Heidegger – which is where he always begins (with an almost palpable bending of the knee for the ‘master’, a rhetorical tremolo and touching of the forelock in his prose) – but in this case specifically with Heidegger’s dogmatic anointing of the Greek physis to be not just nature but being – Badiou translates Heidegger’s ‘constancy of being’ into some of his mathematical set jargon.  He thereby demonstrates the ‘stasis’ of interiority (called inclusion, belonging) underlying his own concept of state and state of the situation.
“What could be more stable than what is, as multiple counted twice in its place, by the situation and the state?  Normality, the maximum bond between belonging and inclusion is well suited to thinking the natural stasis of a multiple.  Nature is what is normal, the multiple re-secured by the state.” (Alain Badiou, Being and Event, London/New York, 2007, pp. 127-128)
One wonders how temporality, historicity, the event could ever enter or interrupt all this normal and natural stability of the state.  Nature, says Badiou following Heidegger, is absolute normality – similar to one of the three dispositifs of Nazihood singled out by Esposito – the absolute normativization of life. (see “The Philosophy of Bíos” in Esposito, Bíos, ibid. p. 11)


Perhaps not surprisingly, Foucault’s followers in particular Agamben – ignore what seems to be a very unambiguous precept of his genealogies of power.  “In order to make a concrete analysis of power relations, we must abandon the juridical model of sovereignty.” (“Society must be defended”, ibid., p. 265)
(Here he also seems to part ways totally with Derrida’s “Force of Law” and the ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority’, as well as The Beast and the Sovereign.  When one thinks the ‘essence’ of power, its concreteness – then only minus the law and the monarchical sovereign.  The king’s head must roll in the discourse of power, says Foucault.)
Agamben must thus try to reconcile the dynamic anti-state (the only living part of the Nazi entity) with some casuistically determined juridical construct called the ‘state of exception’ – so as to rescue his symbiotic duality of “sovereign power and bare life”.  Not even Carl Schmitt can redeem this antiquated model.   
Foucault though in forfeiting the ‘juridical model of sovereignty’ at the same time dispenses with an essential ‘terminological mask’ of power in the form of the sanctioned violence conserved in the law.  Although the so-called ‘state of exception’ in the Third Reich was simply a “society without law, prey of pure caprice (…)” (Adorno, Negative Dialektik, ibid., p. 303) – in a society with law – law itself “conserves terror in society, ready to go back to it at any moment with the help of quotable statutes.” (ibid.)  In either case – there is no need to hypostatize a ‘state of exception’.    
But Foucault’s “genealogy of the modern state” has an obvious entelechy, a predetermined end – that of the Nazi ‘state’ – whose supposed type of power compels him the most – so-called bio-power.  Thus he will present the history or prehistory of biopolitics in quasi-millenarian terms – subtly moulding the millenarian longing for a “day of revenge” - as if it were foretelling the advent of the “new Führer” and “the Third Reich”:  
“Throughout the whole of the Middle Ages, and even later, the theme of perpetual war will be related to the great, undying hope that the day of revenge is at hand, to the expectation of the emperor of the last years, the dux novus, the new leader, the new guide, the new Führer; the idea of the Fifth Monarchy, the third empire or the Third Reich, the man who will be both the beast of the Apocalypse and the saviour of the poor. (…) it’s the two Fredericks – Barbarossa and Frederick II – waiting in their caves for their people and their empires to reawaken; (…)”(“Society must be defended”, ibid., p. 57)


The deep flaw in Foucault’s construction of that shadowy “historico-political discourse” against a “philosophico-juridical discourse” of sovereignty as the sole locus of power, manifests itself especially in his ‘genealogy of hope’.  How can this be a “partisan” discourse of power or resistance ‘from below’, of war against sovereignty and state power, if it merely takes the form of a mass longing for another unknown sovereign – the new Führer and the new empire who will bring salvation to the poor?  Only the Fifth Monarchy Men, an insurrectionary group during the English Civil War and Interregnum, correspond to the idea of resistance to sovereign power – one “that cuts off the king’s head (…) does without a sovereign and denounces him”, (ibid.).


Rather than being a subversive underground history of resistance – Foucault’s ‘other’ discourse – the “historico-political discourse” seems in his presentation to flow directly into what he identifies as Nazi biopower, its Führer and the Nazi mass.


Hitler’s bohemian lifestyle caused Speer to secretly wonder when the Führer ever worked – going to bed at 5:00 am after hours of watching musicals, eating cream cakes and unending monologues to the cronies at Berghof (during which he sometimes nodded off) then waking at 12:00 noon, more concerned with his digestion and Dr. Morell than the state of German armaments. 


In the early days of his career in Munich he groomed himself as a cavalier servente of numerous society ladies, some of whom such as the wife of the piano manufacturer Bechstein were his ardent benefactresses.  The notables of the Nazi party did not always view this approvingly.  Some saw the future Führer as a sponger, a parasite, a womanizer.  No one really knew how Hitler financed his affluent lifestyle – although not yet particularly flashy it certainly allowed him to spend most of his time in cafes, restaurants, upper class salons, the cinema (sometimes 4 movies a day), ride around in his own car and even pay the salary of a chauffeur, bodyguard and other assistants.  When some of the old guard such as Drexler dared to question his finances, he issued an ultimatum – before quitting the party.  The condition for his return – resignation of the party committee, the position of first chairman and dictatorial powers over the party for himself.  Hitler also refused to consider any association with other parties – either ‘Anschluß’ or nothing.   The politics of the engorgement of the adversary made their first appearance.
The opposition collapsed the following day – “castrating itself” in the rush to acknowledge the “dictator”. (See Wulf C. Schwarzwäller, Hitlers Geld, Von armen Kunstmaler zum millionenschweren Führer, Wiesbaden, 2001, pp. 90-91)  They began to address him as “Führer”. The Nazi/Hitler dictatorship is anticipated in the internal cabals of the Nazi party around the person of Hitler – the beginning of his “Byzantine” style which Speer (only later) so condemned and regretted.  This is his first successful ‘coup’, the first declaration of the ‘state of exception’.  As a response to the party’s dissatisfaction with his appropriating, accumulating large private funds, Hitler demands dictator ‘powers’ (diktatorische Machtbefugnisse) in the party.  The money question ends in absolute power of the “Führer principle” – at first in the party itself.   The simple principle that the Führer has all the money he wants, no questions asked was voluntarily inscribed after 1934 in the official mammoth sized double-edged slush fund called the “Adolf Hitler Spende der Deutschen Wirtschaft” (Adolf Hitler Donation of the German Economy), vaguely similar to ‘The Prince’s Trust’.  His most loyal and vicious watchdog – Martin Borman, exclusively administered the fund.  Neither the party nor the state had any jurisdiction over these monies.  The bottomless Croesus fund represented one of the major sources of Hitler’s personal wealth – a figure of billions calculated in today’s currency.  Into it flowed endless tax-free contributions of heavy industry magnates especially Krupp and Thyssen and every other German employer – four times a year.  Thyssen had been the personal fairy godmother of Hitler, Göring and the Nazi Party since the twenties.  Hitler used his private fund for a myriad of purposes and whims: for instance the permanent construction site of his ‘Xanadu’ kingdom Berghof on the Bavarian mountain of Obersalzberg, rewarding old Nazi vassals – so-called ‘old fighters’, Eva Braun’s wardrobe and jewellery (she would go directly to Borman, who decided on this himself), donations to Winifred Wagner, buying up his family’s former homes in his birthplace Braunau and destroying biographical evidence including persons conflicting with his tales in Mein Kampf as well as projects to turn Linz into the Führer’s private city and his art collection supposed to rival the Louvre.  Many of the more extravagant toys bought with this wealth like the teahouse “Adlerhorst” (30,000,000 Reichsmark) built directly into the mountaintop had to be kept secret from the public who liked to see their Führer as a ‘man of the people’ with simple appetites. (Hitlers Geld, ibid., pp. 195 ff)  Hitler tired of his Barbarossian teahouse after a year – it reverted to an aerie for the remainder of the Third Reich.


The work of a tyrant is not labour – it is pure manifestation of will.  The rank and file are the will-less tools of the tyrant – they are the workers of his will, everybody besides him is his subjectless subject.  Whereas he does not work at all.  His is the workless will – or workless work.   There is only one subject in the tyrannical state – one Being who can say “I” – the tyrant himself or the “last man”.
Similarly, the word of the Führer is law – there is no need for a practise or activity of law – it issues fully formed from the Führer’s mouth.  Like Athena from the head of Zeus, the law from the Führer’s mouth, tongue, breath, etc.


The politics of work or action – or type?  Action is key to Arendt’s idea of the political – just as Heidegger begins his Letter on Humanism with the question “What is action?”, referring pointedly to thinking begun in 1936 – and Badiou’s event presupposes a theory of the act of the militant subject.  The event is almost only a ‘pretext’ for the emerging of the militant-subject of what one cannot decide upon – the undecidable character of the event.


In our time, the last man is no man – it is Capital. (the part of no-part?)


With the disappearance of the individual, the form of tragedy disappears as well.  Such a non-individual is no longer happy or unhappy – his drives, passions etc are themselves as commensurable as his availability (replaceability, ‘readiness-to-hand’) for flexible insertion in the production process of the average.  His desires are pre-formed by the “multitude”.  How can they stray far?  The communism of desires has long been enacted, at least since fascism.  Perhaps it is also time to discard the worn out model of tragedy as a ground of philosophy or even truth – still dear to Badiou’s heart as shown by his frequent citing of Aeschylus’s invention of tragedy as one of the great art or truth events of the history of mankind.  But does this event still resonate today as truth?  Or is not late world capitalism a propitious moment to break with the eternal return at least regarding the ‘birth of tragedy’.  Is not tragedy today – and perhaps already in the thought of Schiller, Hölderlin and even Hegel - a mere vehicle of the heroization/glorification of the risk shy middle classes – whose most fearful thoughts circle around the loss of property, status and social death.  In its first revival in German idealism – Greek tragedy at least gave the middle classes a certain dignity in their nascent rebellion against their aristocratic masters.   Tragedy guilds such ordinary private concerns with an aura of antique glory or ‘depth’.  Thus the critique of tragedy would also be one of false bottoms and fake abysses.  As Adorno writes:  “It is my view that it is high time for a critique of the category of tragedy, not as a sublime and permanently valid expression of the human spirit, but as an heirloom from the stock of possessions of the middle classes.” (Theodor W. Adorno, Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason, translated by Rodney Livingstone, Stanford, 2001, p. 187)  One may add that these possessions as usual were passed on as hand-me-downs to the working class – where they were awakened to new spurious life for instance in Brecht’s and Döblin’s petty thieves and murderers intoxicated or electrified with affect or Lukacs’ sedate “Fauststudien”.  The category of tragedy translated into the maudlin dramas of working class passion flowed/escaped directly into the personal myth of Hitler – used as a stock-in-trade of ‘metaphysical’ drama till this day.  A most recent example is the English production of Berlioz’ opera Damnation of Faust performed by ENO (English National Opera) and directed by Terry Gilliam (London Coliseum 2011).  But the stunted Greek tragedy or the underclass back alley ‘drama of fate’ typical of such productions would not be possible if Goethe hadn’t already in his day used a fait divers of a child murderess sentenced to death for murdering her own child, to flesh out his character of Faust’s true love – Marguerite or Gretchen.  In the ENO production not even Mephisto is exempt from being tainted by the atmosphere of a sweaty sleazy lower class ‘nest warmth’ à la Berlin Alexanderplatz or Wings of Desire – at one embarrassing point he shows off his hairy physique and bulging executioner arms in a white sleeveless ribbed undershirt smeared with blood.  Besides “Arbeit macht frei” which flashes across the stage at the opera production’s final moment of epiphany – another motto for Gilliam’s ‘Faust’ would be that folk wisdom “Nothing worse than working for the working class.”


In the case of Hitler, his individuation emerging from the pre-individual primordial bog (miasma) of German collectivity re-collectivized the German entity according to the specifics/specifications of his own physiology.  Between Führer and Volk the bond of Artgleichheit (identity of type) is forged, according to both Schmitt and Heidegger, an imperative (absolute condition) for racial community.  This is what makes him a German hero.  There is only one hero at a time.  There is never room for more than one.  Has any novel ever had more than one?  He is the last tyrant.  There is the hero and there are the parasites of the hero.  And the ‘dark men’ of whom the hero is a parasite.  The hero draws all the disquietude, private individuated restlessness of the ensemble of non-individuals into his one heroic action of Being.  His Being is primary Action – everything else flows from this.  His One Action of Being tranquilises all the private antagonistic disquietude, the ‘Ur-quarrel of earth and world’ (Heidegger); giving the social mass the sensation of collective nirvana, a post-orgasmic state, of being folded in the embrace of Being.  The hero who rises up out of their ranks and who will be carried by them, must have the professional and full-time ability to protect the finite insatiable mass emotion from its decomposing.  In this sense, according to Badiou’s system, such a hero would be the only faithful subject of the event of the ‘mass’.
Naturally this state of being is not a constant; it must be renewed with ever-greater orgasms followed by ever-deeper nirvana.  All further actions of the masses are only mediated via the hero.  Strictly speaking, they do not act at all.  Their collective has become a form of mass autohypnosis.  The Many (pre-individual) and the One (individual) of the Führer is mirrored in the Many and the One of the mass.  Hence the sheer relief of it – being incorporated in the Action Being or Action Body of the Hero gives the gift of healing nature.  If the hero-Führer is an action body for the mass through which they achieve the impossible aporetic state of quiet in unquiet or non-action in action - he bestows upon them this miracle of Eros.  But only under one magical condition – never tell your love.


Nazism was archaic in its “work ethic”.  Surprisingly in the new ‘political theologies’ of today (Agamben, Nancy, Blanchot et al.) work has fallen out of favour.  Instead, the figure of the voyou desœuvré, the ‘inoperative’, the undecided good-for-nothing has become the prototype for the “coming community”.
“The theme of desœuvrement-inoperativeness as the figure of the fullness of man at the end of history – which first appears in Kojève’s review of Queneau, has been taken up by Blanchot and by Nancy, who places it at the very center of his work The Inoperative Community.  Everything depends on what is meant by “inoperativeness”.  It can be neither the simple absence of work nor (as in Bataille) a sovereign and useless form of negativity.  The only coherent way to understand inoperativeness is to think of it as a generic mode of potentiality that is not exhausted (like individual action or collective action understood as the sum of individual actions) in a transitus de potentia ad actum.” (Homo Sacer, ibid., p. 62) 


What then is the voyou desœuvré?  Although Agamben is not the inventor of the term, he attributes to it an almost revolutionary messianic pathos.  Certainly, the voyou is hardly the proletarian consciousness in the Lukacs style, in which the collective act of class-consciousness transforms history.  The figure is first an absence or a void – someone who has no employment, no use in the historical present or only a negative one.  Agamben considers this figure to be an emblem of Aristotelian potentiality, someone whose significance if any is not existent now but may be later - in a future he connotes as ‘messianic’ or borrowing Kojève’s concept, as the ‘end of history’.  But the potentiality he has in mind is not really situated in the future - or only as far as the future is not the potentiality of what could be but of what could have been.  The future implied by Agamben’s idea of potentiality is actually a repetition of what was latent in the past but could not appear because of the past itself.  It is the past, which was in the way of itself.  The ‘simple’ future has the form of the unknown and the new, it must be invented – the ‘past’ future has the form of regret – missed opportunity which emphasizes lack, a sort of ‘almost’ but not quite, not to be confused with Bloch’s “Noch-Nicht”.  In a sense it is quite similar to the backward looking “fidelity to the event” so central to Badiou’s ‘philosophy of history’.  In the same way potentiality is displaced into the past, the voyou could be the retrograde agent of Badiou’s fidelity to the event.
(“Note that the subject of fidelity is, in this way, directly comparable to Agamben’s workless subject.” (see Tim Fisken, “On the Politics of Endless Thought”, online, PDF, p.23))


Is this the real meaning of voyou desœuvré, the ‘model’ of the voyou, the workless dictator Hitler?


The voyou like the event is an “exception” – meaning the figure has no specific place in the contemporary sphere, yet in its negativity defines and exceeds the limit of that sphere towards both the past and the future of that superseded yet unfinished past. 
The voyou is thus also an ‘excessive subject’.
Both Badiou and Agamben seem to exclude any possibility of something ever happening for the first time.  An event is always something, which has happened prior to whatever it is encompassing the “fidelity to the event”.  (Badiou speaks of the event as a rupture – but is it really the case?  The subject constructing itself in its fidelity to such an event, though does not project itself into an unmade future – but back towards something it has later perceived to have been that unrepresented indiscernible element of the state constituting a newness called by Badiou an event.  So the event and consciousness of the event or its subject are distinctly separate (ungleichzeitig) – the event clearly preceding the subject in time.)  Radical political theory and practise is perhaps infinite and inexhaustible but open only in the direction of the past.


Axiom 2:  The exception is the parasite of the rule.
Axiom 2a:  The rule is the parasite of the exception.


Commentary to Axiom 2:


What was ‘presented’ and what was ‘represented’ in “My Night in the Bad Class”? (Silent performance from The Accident Colony, Triptych from the Dark Night of Suburbia)  The Fly-Woman was in the play without being in the play.  Her invisibility was a deepening of the silences of the ‘silent play’.  The play was constructed around her absence/presence.  The physical space, empirical armature of the evental site, was too small to even contain her presence.  Is this the ‘edge of the void’?  If so, then she determines the event “My Night in the Bad Class” in more ways than one -  “the local determination of a site (…) a situation in which at least one multiple on the edge of the void is presented.” (Alain Badiou, Being and Event, ibid., p. 179)
The multiple is “abnormal” – the one on the edge of the void.  She was never dismissed; the play and its night must grow towards her.  The Fly-Woman is the condition of the event “My Night in the Bad Class”.  A site though, according to Badiou, is only retroactively qualified as ‘evental’ by the occurrence of an event.  Badiou’s entire system is retroactive, because the event itself does not or cannot just ‘occur’.  The existence of an event in its own evental site is the result of an “interpretive intervention” happening at a time x subsequent to all that.  In other words only the interpretation from beyond the situation (the grave of the present, each moment a tomb) can “declare” if the event took place or not (ibid., p. 181).
The event is an aftermath of itself, an infinite delay (postponing) of Being.  The event haunts itself.
The Fly-Woman (long green coat and black stockings) is included in the situation but not a member of “My Night in the Bad Class”.  The Blue-Coat Boy (long blue coat and yellow stockings) is neither included nor a member.  He is a parasite of the parasite.
The Fly-Woman has a coat made of a lighter material for the warmer seasons and another rough green coat for the colder seasons.  Both are floor length.  The Blue-Coat Boy has only one long heavy coat for all year round.
They are both versions/phenotypes of ‘weak Messiahs’, not to be confused with the ‘lost messiah’ – weak Messiahs are pure presence, they do not get lost or go missing.  They are unable not to be present.  (“What’s out tonight is lost”, Edna St Vincent Millay, Phil Solomon)





Friday 27 April 2012

Self-Assertion of an English Garden (After-Life Topoi of Nazi Desire) Chapter 6.1.


1.     Il faut cultiver notre jardin   
2.     Pêcheurs de lune
3.     Iterability of the Nazi State (Economy of Genocide)
4.     Growth (and Form/Morphe)
5.     Decay
6.     Pompes Funèbres
6.1.  Type (Model, Example, Tupos)
6.2.  Usus Tyrannus (Interlude)
6.3.  The Ageing of a Note
7.      Critique of Beginnings
8.      Demonology of Defeat 



 
6.     Pompes funèbres


6.1.  Type (Model, Example, Tupos)

The university is a topos like the compound – equally a nomos of the modern – the university is also a nomos of the ancient.  The universitas had the status of an autonomous city in medieval Europe – even before the establishment of the juridical-political form of communitasCommunitas achieved such a distinct form only from the 12th century onward when it became a body literally having the property of itself – belonging to itself.  Like the monastery or other similar exceptional bodies or corporations, the university has always enjoyed the privilege of immunity or its semblance – and perhaps its nemesis ‘auto-immunity’.  All such closed bodies with their self-conceived rules, entities that are ‘laws unto themselves’, dedicated to a certain kind of self-preservation of the founding stock structurally resemble ‘the camp’ and vice versa.  Like the ‘camp’ they are descendents of the ‘household’ or oikos – the extended blood family and their goods and chattels including slaves ruled by despotic lines of absolute obedience to a head. The supreme master or patria potestas was the sole rationale of the household.  He alone determined what constituted its biological survival.
The nomadic household metamorphosed into the colony.  The SS camp-system was the way the Nazi entity territorialized itself and colonised the east – the slave-and-death camps were its colonies.

Biological selection was the norm in the household – such that the exposure of infants and sale of children was nothing unusual; these practises were “unforbidden” throughout antiquity, lasting until as late as A.D. 374 (see Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition, Chicago, 1998, p. 29).   
Biopolitics or the biopolitical paradigm is itself an offspring of the ancient oikos and, as Derrida insists in The Beast and the Sovereign   (Vol. I, Chapter Twelve), – “nothing new”.  The politics of the ‘West’ has always been biopolitics – hence biopolitics is both ancient and modern – certainly not specifically modern, nor the “decisive event of modernity” (Agamben).
   
I do not say the nomos of the modern university is fascist or Nazi-ist – but ask what are the characteristics of the ‘type’, Gestell or Gestalt of the university – its cosmological implications as a ‘technique’ (techne) – like Kafka’s Gericht (court).  Is the university a theatre – a metaphysical theatre as opposed to a nature theatre?  A Theatre of Penance?  Or is it better described as an ‘ontological-hysterical theatre’ with its long running drama of ‘immaculate succession’ in the canon of western metaphysics and all its subplots of priapism, castration, sodomy, bestiality, passive obedience, sovereign madness, impossible love and circumcision neuroses?  The staging of the incestuous duel between the ‘partisans of desire’ and the ‘partisans of the Law’ - its still untitled spectacle?  As an acting out of the “ontological need” (Adorno)?  Or should one rather speak of a “biopolitical need”? (Note: Many thanks to Johan Siebers (IGRS London) who coined this felicitous phrase in a conversation with the author.)   
How is fascist or Nazi desire intrinsic to the formation of the authority of the contemporary ‘discourse of the university’?  Or how is Nazi desire constitutive of the law of this formation?  In other words, what are the possible relations of Nazi desire to this discourse or ‘nomos’ in the sense elucidated by Foucault in The Archaeology of Knowledge: “(…) discourse may in fact be the place for phantasmatic representation, an element of symbolization, a form of the forbidden, an instrument of derived satisfaction (this possibility of being in relation with desire is not simply the fact of the poetic, fictional, or imaginary practice of discourse: the discourses on wealth, on language (langage), on nature, on madness, on life and death, and many others, perhaps, that are much more abstract, may occupy very specific positions in relation to desire).” (Michel Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge, London, 1974, p. 68)

In the word ‘university’ one can hear universal, a universe, a world.  The preoccupation with a ‘new’ universalism in political-philosophical thought of today flows almost subterraneously into the project of fascist/Nazi worldliness or its “transcendental” (Badiou)  – or at the very least an urgent farming of “the legacy of “totalitarianism””, for effects of modernity, whereby Nazism and Heidegger, its chief philosopher, is mainly intended (see Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, “Transcendence Ends in Politics”, in Typography, Stanford, 1998).  Nazism has a philosophical body – philosophy does not have a Nazi-brain.
In the pose of the ‘naïf’ Lacoue-Labarthe asks the deceptively ‘simple’ question: “Is there a possible “politics” that would take account of the thought of Heidegger?” (ibid., p. 270)  He even asks this leading question twice  – having begun his essay with a slightly different formulation: “Is any politics possible that could take into account Heidegger’s thought?” (ibid., p. 267)  The simple answer would be yes – it was Nazism for Heidegger – for Lacoue-Labarthe it assumes the form of an unknown extrapolation of Heidegger’s Nazi commitment projected into the future.  But that would be too simple.  Although since Lacoue-Labarthe poses this question on the basis of documents of Heidegger’s Nazism, especially the “Rectoral Address”, his question becomes almost self-answering.  But he does not mean just what sort of politics were possible then for Heidegger – but what politics in the wake of Heidegger are possible now for us.  ‘Our politics’ is even more tightly knitted to Heidegger and ‘his politics’, because, says Lacoue-Labarthe, only Heidegger even allows us to ask the question – “Under what conditions can the political sway the philosophical?  Is there an unavoidable political overdetermination of the philosophical?  And to what point is the political more powerful than the philosophical?” (ibid., p. 268)  Lacoue-Labarthe’s form of asking the general question of ‘the political’ and its necessary relation to the philosophical can and must, in his view, only be thought through Heidegger’s philosophical politics of Nazism – as if for him Nazism is the only possible form of the relationship between the political and the philosophical.  The model or type of the relation of the philosophical and the political is that unknown x in Heidegger’s thought, “(…) that made possible – or more exactly, (…) did not forbid – the political engagement of 1933?” (ibid.)  Quite obviously it is Lacoue-Labarthe’s hypothesis and conviction that Heidegger’s ‘politics’ is absolutely immanent to his philosophy – and the inaugural address is to be seen in a continuity with the inaugural lecture “What is Metaphysics?” of 1929 and Sein und Zeit.  [In the case of “What is Metaphysics?” – Heidegger emphasizes the continuity of his pre-1933 and post-1933 thought in a quite literal fashion.  The last sentence of the 1929 lecture is the very first sentence of the lecture course Einführung in die Metaphysik from 1935: “Warum ist überhaupt Seiendes und nicht vielmehr Nichts?” (“Why is being(s) at all and not just nothing?”)]
Interestingly (adding to the confusion), another Heideggerian, Esposito, sees Heidegger as being ‘impolitical’ – “(…) Heidegger’s (philosophy) isn’t a political philosophy but, more specifically, the deconstruction of a political philosophy in the thought of community.” (Roberto Esposito, Communitas The Origin and Destiny of Community, Stanford, 2010, p. 92)
      
Whether Heidegger’s philosophy is political or not – he has become a model for the ‘the political’ for a certain incarnation of philosophy – Derrida, Lacoue-Labarthe, Nancy, Agamben, Badiou etc.  But what sort of political?  Considering the seminal text is his inaugural address as rector of the Freiburg University coinciding with the beginning of the Nazi Reich – Heidegger’s ‘politics’ is primarily the politics for and of the university - the self-asserted politics of Geist (Spirit) identified by Heidegger with Being and the State.  In fact only Spirit, in Heidegger’s sense, can guarantee the endurance of the Nazi state beyond the present generation – his most urgent political-philosophical enterprise.  The only need and use of philosophy (and metaphysics) is to reflect upon the state of the “metaphysical people”.  (It is left to the ingenuity of the respective post-Heideggerian thinkers as to how to adapt/translate what Heidegger considered the exclusive ‘spiritual mission’ of the German people and German universities – its hegemonic founding of ‘world’ – to the non-German case.  This asymmetry gives rise to an errant bastard ‘universalism’ ensuing from Heidegger’s Nazism.)

Although it was the dogma of the time – that the state was born in struggle – Heidegger, pointedly citing the “ancient Greek wisdom” of Plato’s Republic at the end of the address, contends that only ‘spirit’ meaning philosophy can perpetuate it: “All that is great stands in the storm …” (Martin Heidegger, The Self-Assertion of the German University and The Rectorate 1933/1934: Facts and Thoughts, Review of Metaphysics, 38:3 (1985:Mar.) p. 480)
The ‘birth’ of the Nazi state is the impetus for Heidegger’s restoration of metaphysics – as the surrogate enduring abode of that state.

One wonders how in some quarters the rumour that Heidegger ended metaphysics still persists.  And what dialectical purposes it serves?  Rather Heidegger re-founded metaphysics with a vengeance.  This refoundation was constitutive of his Nazism and revealed itself in the ontologizing of what Heidegger saw as its ‘dwelling’ – the State.
Lacoue-Labarthe’s major thesis in “Transcendence Ends in Politics” is precisely that “Heidegger’s politics in 1933” and consequently his “Rectoral Address” are absolutely rooted (standing in “a direct line”) in his philosophical project which is: “(…)“the destruction of the history of ontology”; (…) not within the enterprise of a de-limitation (or, even less, of deconstruction) of metaphysics, but within the project of its fundamental instauratio or refoundation.  Heidegger’s politics in 1933, are a clear consequence of the “repetition” of the Kantian “foundation” — and thereby of the resumption of the (Greek) question of the sense of Being.”(ibid., p. 268) 

By way of a ‘diversion’ through Nazism and an immersion in “the national and the social” - the metaphysical becomes ‘the political’ (and vice versa) in Heidegger’s philosophy.  The metaphysical is also the site of the ‘return to the origins’ – to the Greeks – to the ‘greatness of the beginning’ or the supposed archaic inseparability of thinking and being, which Heidegger refers to with the Greek names of logos and physis.  His question of the sense of Being is to determine how all forms of beings/appearings (Seiende) including logos open out undialectically from one origin – Being – thus eliminating ‘at the source’ the separation between subject and object, concept and the non-conceptual.  Nothing is further from ambiguity than Heidegger’s obsession with metaphysics as the permanence and repetition of the ‘great beginning’ of Greek pre-Socratic philosophy.  His aim is to return metaphysics to the moment (in his interpretation) before logos and physis were separated – thus obviating the hegemony of a metaphysics grounded in reason – what Heidegger also calls “intellectualism” (See Martin Heidegger, Einführung in die Metaphysik, Tübingen, 1998 p. 93).
He contrasts these two positions of metaphysics as one of end (in Hegel’s Science of Logic) and of beginning in his own myth of originary Being.  These two points in the history of metaphysics are summarized in two axioms: “Das Ende zeigt sich in der Formel: ανθρωπος = ζωον λογον εχον: der Mensch, das Lebewesen, das die Vernunft als Ausstattung hat.  Den Anfang fassen wir in eine frei gebildete Formel, die zugleich unsere bisherige Auslegung zusammenfaßt: ϕυσις = λογος ανθρωπον εχον: das Sein, das überwältigende Erscheinen, ernötigt die Sammlung, die das Menschsein (acc.) innehat und gründet.” [“The end shows itself in the formula: ανθρωπος = ζωον λογον εχον: man, the living creature/being, equipped with (having the capacity of) reason.  The beginning we summarize in a freely formed formula, which is at the same time a summary of our interpretation so far: ϕυσις = λογος ανθρωπον εχον: Being, the overpowering appearing, compels the gathering (logos, sm), that is immanent to and founds being-human.” (ibid., p. 134)]  Beginning and end become even more elusive as distinctions – because the end is also a part of the Greek beginning – the elevation of logos over being is the movement of Greek philosophy itself.  Heidegger’s ‘beginning’ is all the more ‘free’ – it is a beginning that as such never was.  More Greek than the Greeks – he constructs not a return to the Greek beginning, but a new alternative beginning in which the ‘original sin’ of logos would be cleansed/purged – that it could assume “power over Being in the beginning of Greek philosophy”: “Wie kommt dieser λογος als Vernunft und Verstand zur Herrschaft über das Sein im Anfang der griechischen Philosophie?” [ “How does this λογος as reason and understanding come to hegemony over Being in the beginning of Greek philosophy?” (ibid., p. 94)]
[Commentary: Derrida discusses this passage at length in the 12th Chapter of The Beast and the Sovereign Vol. 1 with the usual servile/obsequious awe (“Seinshörigkeit”: obedience to Sein) he reserves for Heidegger’s pronouncements – elaborating upon the brutality suffered by Being at the hands of Logos as if it were an outstanding atrocity of the ancient world (on a par with the ‘bloodless annihilation’ of Korah).  But just a few pages before that – at the end of the preceding chapter he ‘forgets’ himself (Seinsvergessenheit: forgetting of Being) in his ‘Cartesian’ other when speaking of the “logic of castration”.]




 
A certain kind of contemporary university ‘militancy’ has its origins in the self-assertion model sketched in the inaugural address.  A militant not of everyday political revendications – but a militant of being and its knowledge – an ontological militant of the state-to-come qua spirit – a militancy corresponding to the “ontological desire/need”.  Itself a labyrinth of reification (Verdinglichung) “ontological desire/need” is, as Adorno says – a reified metaphysics of a reified consciousness: “Reified consciousness is a moment in the totality of the reified world; the ontological need its metaphysics, even when according to its doctrinal content, it exploits the same critique of reification, nowadays grown cheap.” (Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialectics, translated by Dennis Redmond, pdf online, p. 102) [“Verdinglichtes Bewußtsein ist ein Moment in der Totalität der verdinglichten Welt; das ontologische Bedürfnis seine Metaphysik, auch wenn diese, ihrem Lehrgehalt nach, die selber wohlfeil gewordene Kritik an Verdinglichung exploitiert.” (Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialektik, Frankfurt, 1982, p. 102)]

The university-militant ranks higher than the mere worker-militant – despite Jünger’s influence, Heidegger does not cede any ground to the ‘worker’: “(…) for the Gestaltung, in the Address, the figural conferring of sense, is never for a moment “work” but is “knowledge”—and knowledge as techne.  In the same way the Gestalt is not the Worker but the Philosopher (…)” (Lacoue-Labarthe, ibid. p. 296) Heidegger’s is the thought of the political that allows the School Philosopher (“the Philosopher-Tyrant” of Heidegger’s Plato) to conceive of himself qua School Philosopher as the militant of knowledge (“essence of science”) or as Badiou would say ‘truth’.  Badiou regularly, habitually speaks of “Heidegger’s thought in its militant national-socialist dimension” – as if wishing to inculcate in the reader the normality of such a ‘militancy’ – he does not really call any other philosopher-politico besides Heidegger a ‘militant’ – with the poignant exception of Paul, Badiou’s archetypical ‘militant’.  Badiou’s other two “dispositions” of the last century have no personal representative -  “Stalinist Marxism” (Russia) and “Anglo-Saxon analytic philosophy” (the United States) – certainly no ‘militant’ of their own.  Thus, according to Badiou’s theory of the truth process – only Heidegger, the “national-socialist militant”, representing Nazi Germany (the third place), is a subject of truth.  His ‘militancy’ was his ‘wager’ or ‘belief’ that “Hitler’s advent” was “the moment at which thought had finally confronted the planetary reign of technology, or the moment, as he put it in his Rectoral Address, in which ‘we submit [ted] to the distant command of the beginning of our spiritual-historical existence’.” (Alain Badiou, “The (Re)Turn of Philosophy Itself”, Conditions, London/New York, 2008, pp. 8-9)
This moment could be seized in a ‘dialectical image’ – Heidegger’s Nazi militancy is the head of Hitler on the body of Heidegger – but not the head of Heidegger on the body of Hitler.

Such ‘militant’ politics though is not of the university as an institution among others – but the university, transporting/catapulting itself to the world stage (or stage of ‘world’), is the medium of the political on its highest level (‘archi-political’), that of Heidegger’s Nazi ‘polis’ – and as such is the guardian of the continuity of the Führerstaat – the ‘race’ to come (like Derrida’s à venir).  Lacoue-Labarthe is seduced by what appears to him as the mood and mise en scène of ancient tragedy in the rhetorical dramaturgy of the “Rectoral Address”: “The University campus could almost be seen as the desert where prophecy takes place, and its rector, if I may be forgiven this redundancy, as the Tiresias of a political tragedy.” (ibid., p. 278)  One would better compare Heidegger with a grand inquisitor addressing an ecclesiastical tribunal.


[Commentary: Führer should be seen as a generic concept – Heidegger alludes to the ‘Führer-principle’ (enshrined in the “New Student Law” of May 1st 1933), one must educate ‘führerische Menschen’ (führer-ish people) – he was called during his rectorship – the Rektor-Führer.  In his lecture series “Hegel, über den Staat” from 1934 Heidegger warns his listeners:  “Unser Staat wird in 60 Jahren bestimmt nicht mehr vom Führer getragen, was dann aber wird, steht bei uns.” (“In sixty years, our state will surely no longer be led by the Führer; therefore what it becomes then will depend on us.”, from Martin Heidegger, Hegel, über den Staat, unpublished lecture, cited in Emmanuel Faye, Heidegger The Introduction of Nazism into Philosophy in Light of the Unpublished Seminars of 1933-1935, Yale University, 2009, p. 212 and p. 386)
Heidegger did at least allow for the possibility of Hitler and himself becoming centenarians.] 


Derrida connects Heidegger’s ‘metaphysics’ and ‘politics’ in a slightly different manner – Nazi self-assertion is itself spirit or ‘spiritualized’ – so the originary concept of the political, prior to its ‘descent’ or bursting forth into the State, is itself spirit.
Universalism presumes or posits a world where differences no longer matter or what Badiou refers to as ‘one world’.  Somehow this world is identified with one (world) state and its sovereignty – or an ideal state in the Platonic sense (Badiou’s ontological state which coincides irredeemably with the historical state) – the pure immanence of a ‘world state’ or ‘empire’.  Nothing can subsist outside of this state/empire/world – it tolerates no exteriority.  In the concept of ‘one world’ resistance is also abolished at the ‘ontological’ level. 

Although a Heideggerian like Granel, sounding almost like Adorno, acknowledges a “desperate resistance (of) the singular (…) to its death sentence in the concept.”  Commenting on Reiner Schürmann’s Broken Hegemonies he writes: “(…) but this attraction of the universal is always compounded by a kind of reverse pull, due to the fact that we can never entirely blind ourselves to the desperate resistance the singular puts up to its death sentence in the concept. (…) The aim is to show that the singularity’s refusal to let itself be absorbed into the concept “belabours”, “works at” the latter at the very heart of its operation, destabilizes it, and ends up wrecking it.” (Gérard Granel, “Untameable Singularity” in Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal, Vol. 19, No 2–Vol. 20, No 1, 1997, p. 215-228) 

 
How inconceivable today in the age of ‘the political’ under the auspices/protection of a world hegemony of Being – is the ‘cosmopolitanism’ of the Renaissance ‘l’uomo universale’ – for whom exile held no terror – quite the opposite: the Renaissance individual experienced the world as Ubi bene, ibi patria.  Cosmopolitanism is the highest development of the Renaissance individual – Dante who himself was punished by exile and refused to return to Florence under dishonourable conditions wrote: “My homeland is the world as a whole!” (cited in Jacob Burckhardt, Die Kultur der Renaissance in Italien, Stuttgart 1988 (reprint of the edition Leipzig, 1869), p. 102)
The mournful ontological ‘homelessness’ (Heimatlosigkeit) conjured up so dolefully by Heidegger in his Letter on Humanism is the condition when beings are abandoned by Being and are thus not unsurprisingly oblivious of Being. The only ‘cure’ he prescribes for the “Weltschicksal” (worldfate) of homelessness is a penitent acceptance of the vows of poverty as a “shepherd of being”.  The world historical background of this ‘homelessness’ in 1949, year of the publication of The Letter on Humanism is most obvious.  In it he predictably condemns Renaissance ‘humanism’ as a return to the Roman (romanitas) – Roman civilization and the Renaissance is as anathema for him as it was for Ruskin of The Stones of Venice.  Heidegger’s “Greek-ness” is also closer to “Gothic scholasticism” and homo barbarus than it is to any sort of Hellenism. 
He distances himself from Winckelmann, Goethe and Schiller and their idea of imitating the Greeks (‘in order to make ourselves inimitable’) in favour of Hölderlin.  “The worldhistorical thinking” Hölderlin, his designated poet of Being, shows in his poem “Andenken” (Remembrance) is more of the beginning and of the future than the “mere cosmopolitanism” of Goethe.  Hölderlin had another relation to Greek-ness (Griechentum) (although the poem “Andenken” speaks not of Greece but of memories, of France – “the gardens of Bordeaux” and the sea) – essentially other than humanism – and it is this other relation which caused those “young Germans” who knew him, when “confronted with death” to think or be something other than what was held to be “typically German” – the image is borrowed from the first World War when every German soldier was supposed to have had Stefan George in his ‘Tornister’ (knapsack). (See Letter on Humanism, in Pathmarks, translated by Frank A. Capuzzi, 1949, p. 258)  The Wehrmacht soldier or SS presumably had Hölderlin or Heidegger in his.  When Heidegger speaks of Greece he seems to mean not a place nor even a civilization but a certain kind of holiness – the numinous – the mysterium tremendum et fascinans  - which he calls “das Heilige des Vaterlandes” (the holiness of the Fatherland).  The poet, in Heidegger’s interpretation, although he stays at home in Swabia, has not forgotten Greece, but has received a sign from afar (the spectral return of a greeting) to call to the holiness of the fatherland and under its highest protection to make himself at home (heimisch).  The ‘holiness of the fatherland’ becomes simply ‘the holy land’ or the homeland of fidelity in Badiou’s devotional text in Being and Event (Meditation 25) on Heidegger’s ‘master’ interpretation of Hölderlin.  As a revenant of Jargon der Eigentlichkeit (Adorno), Badiou echoes Heidegger who ventriloquizes Hölderlin, in lighting up the faded sacrality of the German “homeland” with Greek ‘fire’.  Drawing from this fake portmanteau-religiosity (the chimera of Greek-German soil-rootedness) – Badiou finds a primitive source for his own idea of fidelity – “native loyalty”.  Hitler did in fact briefly consider using the ancient chemical weapon ‘Greek Fire’ in the final defence of Berlin.  Badiou could have just as easily quoted the SS motto - Meine Ehre heißt Treue (my honour is loyalty) – or the slogan of ‘Nibelungentreue’ so essential to Nazi propaganda towards the end of the war, for a more recent historical appearance/manifestation of German fidelity.  Contemporary European thought has entrapped itself somewhere in an eternal interwar Europe – so that again one could say, as did Döblin in an introduction to Heine’s Germany, A Winter Fairy Tale, “Der “Faust” geht schrecklich um.  (Nennt sich auch “Hölderlin”.)
[“Faust” is haunting terribly.  Also calls himself “Hölderlin”. Einleitung von Alfred Döblin (1923), Deutschland, Ein Wintermärchen, Hamburg, 1844, p. XVI]
One wonders what this holy German homeland and its “German fidelity” are to the French Badiou?  What is the ‘evental site’ to which the Greeks are made to give their blessing?

But do the historical Greeks really substantiate Heidegger’s or Badiou’s claims about them or those of Hölderlin’s unique affinity with them?
As Burckhardt remarks – the Greeks (to whom Heidegger appeals) did not recognize this malaise of ‘homelessness’, nor were they overly attached to the ‘homeland’ – the ‘golden age’ of classical Greece tended more toward cosmopolitanism:  “Übrigens ist der Kosmopolitismus ein Zeichen jeder Bildungsepoche, da man neue Welten entdeckt und sich in der alten nicht mehr heimisch fühlt.  Er tritt bei den Griechen sehr deutlich hervor nach dem peloponnesischen Kriege; Platon war, wie Niebuhr sagt, kein guter Bürger und Xenophon ein schlechter; Diogenes proklamierte vollends die Heimatlosigkeit als ein wahres Vergnügen und nannte sich selber απολις, wie man bei Laertius liest.” (“By the way, cosmopolitanism is a sign of every cultural epoch in which new worlds are discovered and one no longer feels at home in the old ones.  It was noticeably present amongst the Greeks after the Peloponnesian wars; Plato was, as Niebuhr says, not a good citizen and Xenophon was a bad one; Diogenes proclaimed emphatically that homelessness was a true pleasure and called himself απολις as one can read in Laertius.”, Jacob Burckhardt, ibid., p. 427)  If that was true of the ancient Greeks, why should one still long today to be in “the homeland of this historical dwelling” which is “nearness to being”? (See Heidegger, Letter on Humanism, ibid.) 
        
The unspoken or euphemistically phrased questions of contemporary thinkers of ‘political ontology’ (a ‘master-discourse’ of today’s university), revolve about the conscious and unconscious aim to reformulate the history of Western metaphysics and Western politics (of the State), (which they tend to collapse into one), so as to make Nazism (to a lesser degree Italian fascism) appear intrinsic to the movement of logos of world(s), or as a historical necessity, an agent and inevitable consequence of ‘modernity’.  Although defined variously as a “state of exception” (Agamben), “the unnameable” (Badiou), or myth (Lacoue-Labarthe and Nancy) – Nazism is paradoxically normalized within the continuity/continuum of ‘the political’ or genealogy of states – de-exceptionalized, made nameable, a norm. 

Jean-Luc Nancy presents this proposed continuity in one of the most extreme forms.  In his conception, the perpetrators of Auschwitz, the defenders of “super-representation”, were not Nazi Germany and its collaborators, but quite simply “the West”:  “At Auschwitz, the West touched the will to present itself that which is outside presence.  Hence it also touched the will to a representation without remainder (…) This means that it was right in the midst of our Western history — once again, without one having to pose it as a destined or mechanical necessity — that this “exact opposite,” this contorted and revolting contraction, suddenly appeared and unleashed its fury. (…) at Auschwitz, the West was exacting revenge upon itself and upon its own opening — the opening, precisely, of [re] presentation.” (Jean-Luc Nancy, “Forbidden Representation”, in The Ground of the Image, Fordham University Press, 2005, p. 43)
According to Nancy’s ‘vision’, Auschwitz ultimately had nothing to do with the genocide of the European Jews carried out by Nazi Germany, with the complicity of the conquered vassal populations of Europe (like the Vichy French, Croatians, Ukrainians, Lithuanians etc), nor with the abortive Nazi empire; – from his ‘non-Hegelian’ ‘non-mechanical’ world historical perspective, this particular German physical historical genocide conducted within and behind their geopolitical militarized expansion drive vanishes into the internal settling of metaphysical accounts of ‘the West’ with itself.  Quite simply the material object of this particular history has been erased – and with it history itself. 
In other words, for Nancy Auschwitz is a universal character-type in the history of Western metaphysics.  Or perhaps its deus ex machina?  Nancy’s ploy is doubtless a triumph of non-representation. 

Another name for this ‘new’ genealogy (dating variously from the 18th century or from time immemorial) incorporating Nazism as its ‘apocalyptic culmination’ (Esposito) is ‘biopolitics’.  Positing a trajectory issuing forth/beginning from Nazism, Esposito introduces a third ‘mediating’ element into the conjunction of bio(logy) and politics – that of technology or technique.
Nazism is politics, which is immediately also technology:
 “(…) the modification of bíos by a part of politics identified with technology [tecnica], was posed for the first time (in a manner that would be insufficient to describe as apocalyptic), precisely in the antiphilosophical and biological philosophy of Hitlerism.”(Roberto Esposito, Bíos Biopolitics and Philosophy, Minneapolis, 2008, p. 11)  One hears echoes in Esposito of Heidegger’s salute to the “inner truth and greatness of the movement” interpolated in his Introduction to Metaphysics from 1935 – “What today is bandied about absolutely as the philosophy of National Socialism, but has not the slightest to do with the inner truth and greatness of this movement (namely the encounter between technicity on the planetary level and modern man) (…)” (Einführung in die Metaphysik, ibid., p. 152).

[Commentary: The view that technology was a peculiar destiny of the Nazi dictatorship must have been a commonplace of that time.  Speer uses the same argument, but as extenuating circumstances for the effective brutality of the regime – in his final address as an accused to the Nuremberg Military Tribunal in 1946.  Speaking as the “most important representative of the technocracy” – he speaks not of his personal guilt nor of the guilt of the regime but offers his ‘objective’ analysis of the use Hitler and his dictatorship made of technology. “Die Diktatur Hitlers war die erste Diktatur eines Industriestaates dieser Zeit moderner Technik, eine Diktatur, die sich zur Beherrschung des eigenen Volkes der technischen Mittel in vollkommener Weise bediente…Durch Mittel der Technik, wie Rundfunk und Lautsprecher, konnten achtzig Millionen Menschen den Willen eines Einzelnen hörig gemacht werden.(…)Die verbrecherische Geschehen dieser Jahre war nicht nur eine Folge der Persönlichkeit Hitlers.  Das Ausmaß dieser Verbrechen war gleichzeitig darauf zurückzuführen, daß Hitler sich als erster für ihrer Vervielfachung der Mittel der Technik bedienen konnte.” (
Hitler’s dictatorship was the first dictatorship of an industrial nation of this time of modern technology, a dictatorship, which used technical means in a perfect fashion for the purpose of ruling its own people…Through the means of technology, like radio and loudspeakers, eighty million people could be made to serve (obey) the will of one single individual. (…) The criminal events of these years were not just a result of the personality of Hitler.  The extent of these crimes was at the same time attributable to Hitler being the first to have used the means of technology for their multiplication.”, Albert Speer, Erinnerungen, Frankfurt-Berlin, 1969, pp. 521-522)

The means of technology also made it possible, according to Speer, to hide the enterprise of mass murder ‘in the open’ amidst the humdrum whirring of the Big Machine. 

Missing though in Speer’s causal chain of dictatorship - technology (radio) – absolute subservience of the will of 80,000,000 Germans to the will of one – is the prior attunement of those Germans to what was conveyed in those radio broadcasts and their willingness to carry out the implicit and explicit commands.  The entire question of agency of the individual is shifted to the sphere of the operation of a vast machine.  Speer makes it seem as if technology itself compelled the German mass to obey the will of its Führer and the immensity of crimes that this entailed.  Strange that the Nuremberg Tribunal judges representing the victorious powers – all highly industrialized nations – should have been impressed by such a technological determinist excuse for the functioning mode of the Nazi state.  If technology alone had been the cause of this anomalous bondage of Führer and Volk – why did this form of absolute obedience of the mass and their register of mass crimes not arise throughout the whole industrialized world?

As one is not quite sure when Heidegger added this parenthesis to Introduction to Metaphysics – it is not impossible he knew Speer’s speech to the war crimes’ court, especially since it was broadcast on the radio.]

Strikingly, in the “encounter between technicity (…) and modern man” in Heidegger’s phrase, technicity comes first, as if prior and dominant of “modern man”.  Esposito follows a typical Heideggerian strategy (exemplified in his Bremen lectures of 1949) of dissolving Nazism and whatever politics it was or is within/into a general overpowering ‘planetary’ paradigm of technology.
Heidegger’s name for this solution of Nazism suspended in technology is techne or Ge-stell.   By turning Nazism into a branch (or quintessence, inner truth) of technology, Esposito (like Heidegger) opens it a path of contamination to the culture at large.  Nazism’s supposed ‘originality’ (being the first of its kind), in this scheme, is at the same time identical with what makes it the ‘rightful heir’ of the Enlightenment – science, modern forms of governance and (bio)policing.  Nazism is neutralized as the objective will of technology.  Its ‘paroxysms’ become an essential conjuncture in the history of metaphysics, now equated with techniques of policing or administration (Derrida’s “spirit of the police”), a ‘scientific’ model of government.  Heidegger leads the way in showing how technology (Technik) is itself a “form of truth (…) grounded in the history of metaphysics” equated with “the history of being”. (Heidegger, Letter on Humanism, ibid., p. 259). (Horkheimer would refer to this “form of truth” as inferior “subjective reason” – one could also call it ‘equipmental’; see The Eclipse of Reason, 1947)  Imitating the procedure of Jünger in Der Arbeiter – but apparently paraphrasing Hegel, Heidegger reifies the subjective activity of ‘labour’, as conceived in Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit, through which the real is objectified in labour experienced as subjectivity – first as the “essence of materialism” which he then in a second fetishizing moment hides in “the essence of technology” (reminiscent of the “essence of science” in the Rectoral Address).  Labour is something technology qua being has objectified rather than technology being the objectification (alienation) of labour.

“The modern metaphysical essence of labour” and its subjectivity, whereby all beings (Seiende) appear as the material of labour, vanishes without remainder into the “essence of technology” – and as such is dignified with the status of a “destiny within the history of being” (seinsgeschichtliches Geschick) and from there traced back to the Greek paradigm of techne and then to aletheia meaning the rendering manifest of beings (Seiende) – with the reflux of beings the circle of the “unconditioned production” of Being is closed. (ibid.)  

‘Biopolitical’ domination or hegemony takes the direct (immediate) form of the ‘technological’ subsumption or seizing of the biological matter (bíos) of the population.  The population in this model is reduced to the status of biological raw material/data at the disposal of government in particular hegemonic medicine as the sovereign arbiter of life and death.  Biopolitics becomes thus a variation of both the myth of Nazi ‘science’ and Nazi ‘politics’. 

[Commentary:  In a lucid moment Esposito demonstrates his awareness of what such Nazi ‘science’ or ‘medicine’ was worth.  Referring to an implicit confusion in the designation of what biology specifically means in so-called Nazi biopolitics, he offers a crucial elucidation:  “As long as we speak of biology we remain on a level of discourse that is far too general.  In order to get to the heart of the question, we need to focus our attention on medicine.  We know the role that Nazi doctors played in the extermination effected by the regime. (…) I am not speaking solely about experiments on “human guinea pigs” or anatomical findings that the camps directly provided prestigious German doctors, but of the medical profession’s direct participation in all the phases of mass homicide: from the singling out of babies and then of adults condemned to a “merciful” death in the T4 program, to the extension of what was called “euthanasia” to prisoners of war, to lastly the enormous therapia magna auschwitzciense: the selection on the ramp leading into the camp, the start of the process of gassing, the declaration of being deceased, the extraction of gold from the teeth of the cadavers, and supervision of the procedures of cremation.  No step in the production of death escaped medical verification. (…) If ultimate power wore the boots of the SS, supreme auctoritas was dressed in the white gown of the doctor. (…) In the no-man’s-land of this new theo-biopolitics, or better theo-zoo-politics, doctors really do return to be the great priests of Baal, who after several millennia found themselves facing their ancient Jewish enemies, whom they could now finally devour at will.” (Bíos, ibid., pp. 113-114)]   

All of this assumes that man is a strictly ‘biologically defined species’ (and that biology is restricted to the ‘human’).  Biopower then acts without resistance upon a ready-made passive biological/genetic aggregate, which is neither human nor animal (but prior to and beyond both), has neither drives nor desires nor ‘plasticity’ – it is ‘mere life’.  ‘Life’ becomes a metaphysical concept for biopower, itself a singular mutation of positivism: “(…) the process by which, (…) man (or the State for him) in modernity begins to care for his own animal life, and by which natural life becomes the stakes in what Foucault called biopower.” (Giorgio Agamben, The Open Man and Animal, Stanford, 2004, p. 12)

For Badiou Nazism is necessary to a concept of a ‘limit’ for truth under the condition of politics – this despite his apparent refusal to grant it the status of an ‘event’ – tacitly Nazism is as much an event for him as ’68 if not more so.  Nazism figures as an example of the “unnameable” – one of the essential four axes of the “becoming” of a truth.  Hence Nazism for Badiou is not just a particular truth – it is one of the constituents of the becoming of any ‘political’ truth.  The “unnameable” of Badiou’s truth process is also indispensable for the “ethics of truth” which must recognize the unnameable as a limitation of its path.
Badiou groups Nazism most insouciantly with other extreme limit points of his designated truth processes:  “Finally, the unnameable is the central motif of the thought of the political that wishes to submit Nazism to thought; as it is of the poet who explores the limits of the force of language; as it is for the mathematician who looks for the undefinables of a structure; as it is for the person in love tormented by what love bears of the sexual unnameable.”(Alain Badiou, “Philosophy and Truth” Infinite Thought, London, 2004, p. 68)

The combination of the first and fourth unnameables yields something, which might be called a Badiouist version of unrequited “Nazi desire”.   
The biological body concealed/sequestered in the unnameable of the political thought of Nazism is not just the body of ‘mere life’, will-less object of sovereign power - it is a sexually tormented one, a body with desire. The protagonist’s sexual hallucinations of Hitler whilst masturbating or dreaming in Genet’s Pompes Funèbres and his real phantasm of feasting upon the corpse of his dead lover, the Résistance hero, are poetic evidence of this truth of the sexually unnameable or Nazi desire.   Where the unnameable of the political or Nazism converges with the unnameable of the sexuated body it brings to light a matrix of the biopolitical residing in Badiou’s axis of “becoming a truth”.

Agamben expresses his perceived necessity of Nazism for political thought most saliently at the conclusion of his Homo Sacer.  His final thoughts bring him to the parallel questions of politics and metaphysics.  Using the Greek term on haplon for Being – he refers at the end to the “Heideggerian definition of Dasein”, concluding that one is compelled to see in this definition the key to the inner relatedness of politics and metaphysics.  “Here attention will also have to be given to the analogies between politics and the epochal situation of metaphysics.  Today bios lies in zoē exactly as essence, in the Heideggerian definition of Dasein, lies (liegt) in existence.” Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer Sovereign Power and Bare Life, Stanford, 1998, p. 188)
But what is Agamben’s prime example of the “interlacement of zoē and bios”, so determinate of our contemporary life as “animals whose life as living beings is at issue in their politics (Foucault)”(ibid.)? 
What are the historical precedents of this union of bios and zoē appearing to us now as our political ‘fate’?
“Yet how can a bios be only its own zoē, how can a form of life seize hold of the very haplos that constitutes both the task and the enigma of Western metaphysics?” (ibid.) The prototype answering the riddle posed by Agamben does not come as a surprise – he supplies the answer only a few pages before the question.  The form of life that fulfils these ‘Oedipal’ requirements is the Führer:  “The Führer’s body is, in other words, situated at the point of coincidence between zoē and bios, biological body and political body.  In his person, zoē and bios incessantly pass over into each other.” (ibid., p. 184)  
  
[Commentary: How does Agamben’s biopolitical Führer-body differ from the body of royal incest characterized by Deleuze and Guattari in Anti-Oedipus?  The body of royal incest is also intensely exposed, a nakedness beyond the body, and must glue to itself not just all bodies of subjects but all organs of these bodies to his own incest body.
“(…) the despotic signifier aims at the reconstitution of the full body of the intense earth that the primitive machine had repressed, but on new foundations or under new conditions present in the deterritorialized full body of the despot himself.  This is the reason that incest changes its meaning or locus, and becomes the repressing representation. (…) all the organs of all the subjects, all the eyes, all the mouths, all the penises, all the vaginas, all the ears, and all the anuses become attached to the full body of the despot, as though the peacock’s tail of a royal train, and that they have in this body their own intensive representatives.” (Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, Anti-Oedipus Capitalism and Schizophrenia, Minneapolis, 1983, p. 210) 
As the despotic signifier the royal incest body is also the body of the command (Führerwort hat Gesetzeskraft).]

A Nazi university is the inversion (of signs) and complement to the Nazi mass.  Movement-Party-State.  Between all three.  (Although the integrity of the fascist/Nazi ‘Total State’ is rather a phantom (spectral) wish of the ‘school’ discourse of political ontology – the ontological block – than a historical reality.)  The pedagogical militant or the mastered master.  Mussolini was the grand educator – il duce.  He admired Lenin whom he considered an artist – whose material was people.
Mussolini is himself a type – of the fascist leader – example and type.

He expresses, testifies to the fascist desire (conatus) to form (fashion) the type of the mass – the mass is not just a quantitative aggregate as found in situ (this would be some kind of philistine democratic heap) – each particle of the fascist mass must bear the type, be the type of that which as a whole (never complete, always open to more mass) will eventually be (given infinite time or future – this is the rule ‘und so weiter’/and so forth of the mass) one type of the same or the same type.
The fascist desire of the leader inscribes itself upon the body of the mass – so that their desire becomes “the desire of the despot’s desire” (Deleuze/Guattari).  And by extension – their body becomes his ‘new’ full body of desire.
The electoral democratic mass is constructed quantitatively – by counting, not as a congregation of bodies in a place.  Nazism and fascism in their cult of the movement and the adulation of the leader corporealizes the mass – and the idea of the mass.  The movement then must come to rest and be fixed in its place.  Leni Riefenstahl’s film of the Nuremberg ParteitagTriumph of the Will shows the ideal of the mass congregated in one place and in univocal simultaneous worship of the leader.  It is not enough for the mass to be biologically racially identical – this is potentially also merely a countable quantity – sine nomine vulgus.  The Nazi/fascist mass must be disposable, visible and movable and presented in one place.  Film was an ideal medium for this presentation of the Nazi mass as the “common place” in the sense of Paul’s interpretation of Aristotle’s koinonia.
The congregation of the faithful in Mecca is another example of one single mass body gathered in one place of ecstatic worship.

These phenomena would seem to correspond to Foucault’s second phase of the “seizure of power over the body” identified as the “technology of power” or biopolitics, entailing a “massifying” of the body.  “So after the first seizure of power over the body in an individualizing mode, we have a second seizure of power that is not individualizing but, if you like massifying, that is directed not at man-as-body but at man-as-species.” (Michel Foucault, “Society must be Defended” Lectures at the Collège de France, 1975-76, New York, 2003, p. 243)  But his definition of biopolitics here as a technology of power in other words sovereignty over a passive massified species is not yet able to grasp the fascist/Nazi mass as a sovereign technology of power for itself.  Power (for Foucault) finally is always directed from above to below – that those below – the biopolitical mass – are the impetus/engine of power (not resistance) cannot be thought with such a concept.  Perhaps one could speak then of a third seizure of power over the body – when the massified body of man-as-race fuses with the technology of subjugation in the Nazi entity – to become not passive objects of power, but the operatives of a totalizing ‘will to power’.  This would be the mass or Volk as envisioned by Heidegger seen through his interpretation of Ernst Jünger’s “type” of the worker.  As “self-assertion” Dasein becomes the equivalent of ‘pure energy’ – an energy immanent to the Nazi strategy for acquiring or transforming power.  It is the Nazi ‘physics’ (physis) of power of the ‘metaphysical people’.  Such a physics of power has abandoned any conventional notions of governance or self-governance.  There is no time for that.  Nazism constitutes (in its absolute sense) – an absurd impossible physical-spiritual apparatus – an undifferentiated body of power without any resistance, invalidating Foucault’s maxim – where there is power, there is resistance.  The congenital flaw of this apparatus – such a resistanceless body of power rapidly converts to total stasis or inertia.  Self-assertion of the selfless mass is the utopian expression for the Nazi body of power situated beyond resistance – or that absolute (total) body of power, which ‘gives’ itself the gift of resistance.  If one can speak of mythology – the “Nazi Myth” is a myth of physics (physis).

In a rather unlikely place in his writings, where Heidegger attempts to press the work of art into the service of his philosophy of being – he confirms this miracle of resistance-less power, or in his term ‘self-assertion’ which belongs to being and not to self.  Speaking of the Ur-binary of world and earth and their quarrel, Heidegger locates ‘self-assertion’ – a word implying resistance at least to what is not self - ‘deep’ in enclosure (Verborgenheit), authenticity (Ursprünglichkeit) and origin (Herkunft).
Im wesenhaften Streit jedoch heben die Streitenden, das eine je das andere, in die Selbstbehauptung ihres Wesens.  Die Selbstbehauptung des Wesens ist jedoch niemals das Sichversteifen auf einen zufälligen Zustand, sondern das sich aufgeben in die verborgene Ursprünglichkeit der Herkunft des eigenen Seins.” (Martin Heidegger, “Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes” in Holzwege, Frankfurt, 1977, p. 35)   [“In essential strife, however, the opponents raise each other into the self-assertion of their essences.  This self-assertion of essence is, however, never a rigid fixation on some condition that happens to be the case, but rather a surrendering into the hidden originality of the source of one’s own being.” “The Origin of the Work of Art” in Off the Beaten Track, Cambridge, 2002, pp. 26-27]
Heidegger performs a typical switch in which self-assertion turns into its opposite (or rather the semblance turns into its opposite semblance) – self-assertion becomes surrendering of self to the hidden authenticity of the origin of one’s proper being – all three terms (hidden authenticity, origin and proper being) form a crescendo of the same.  Such surrendering of self within essential conflict translates into the “presencing” of rest – or it brings presence to rest.  Self-assertion diffuses through turbulence of strife to presence of rest.
The stasis overcoming this turbulence of strife as its essence Heidegger calls the “resting-in-itself” of the work (“Insichruhen des Werkes”, “Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes” in Holzwege, ibid. p. 35).
If fascism/Nazism is an event constructed by the obscure subject – in the view of Adorno there is not a beyond from which to interpret this event.  It is at no time representable.  Fascism/Nazism in its ‘oscillation’ is excluded from its own site.  Here is where it shows its origins, that it has a cyclical or non-specific negative character like capital – the being that is always what it is not at any particular moment in its cycle – also a kind of immaterialism.  Capital like its fascist/Nazi spiritual other produces not only commodities and value, but both produce and reproduce their cyclical being itself.  The fascist/Nazi cycle is at the same time the destruction of value as a primary immaterial commodity.  Is the destruction of value also a destruction of meaning – or the meaning (sense) of being?  The name forces (imposes) an amorphous sameness on whatever it denotes – even the meanings, which exceed the body of signifieds.  The despotic signifiers ‘fascism’ or ‘Nazism’ denote more than what one historically associates with them, although it is a material complex arising in history; once the bodies of the signifiers fascism and Nazism exist they readily move beyond (exceed) all their own historical limitations.  By going beyond these historical limitations they also tend to destroy their historical meanings. 

In a passage in his “Talk on Jünger” – Heidegger both invokes and discounts the demographic inert quantity of the population – 80 million Germans. 
“The question of who the eighty million [Germans] are is not to be resolved on the basis of what their ancestors created but according to what they themselves are able to know and want as a mission for the future, on which basis only then can it be assessed whether they are worthy to invoke their ancestors.  In the next zone of decision, the struggle concerns world power alone, and not so much in the sense of the mere possession of power, as in the capacity for maintaining, within power, power as essence of reality, and that always means: to increase it.” (cited in Faye, ibid., pp. 291-292)

The quantity of the mass (80 million Germans) is a mere facticity – but does not of itself count as power.  Power in this epoch of Heidegger’s thinking was one of the numerous (perhaps numberless) synonyms of being.  Obviously for the Nazi/fascist mission of the conquest of ‘world power’ it is not sufficient to situate power in the state alone – the power, which fulfils “a new truth of being”, is prior to and constitutes the possibility of any state “technology of power”.  The mass for Heidegger is both quantitative and a body of will to power – in its quantitative aspect it represents a race, an aggregate of physical characteristics, an approximation of what could be regarded as a national demographic and genetic pool.  But in this phase it is most distant from world power.  It is also distant from world power as such because it is not the decision of the masses, which is crucial – rather the “premonitions of a few important warriors” (Heidegger writes this in January 1940) about a “change in the way of possessing world power” which have launched the epochal contest with the English and American “democratic “empires”” (no mention of the Soviet Union – the real threat, or France – considered an eclipsed power).  The masses ‘know’ and ‘want’ their mission only through knowing and wanting what has been decided in the ‘zone of decision’ of their leaders (Heidegger includes himself no doubt).  By synchronizing their wants with those of their leaders they gather themselves within the formation of the new truth of being/power.  The future of the new power or being is not short.  Heidegger envisions a span of “a century or more” – it is for this future that the German Volk is embarking on its “struggle”.  As opposed to the “Western powers (who) fight to save the past: we struggle for the formation of a future.” (“Talk on Jünger”, January 1940, cited in Faye, ibid.)  The power, as it comes directly as a “gift or a privation of Being itself” will have also been preceded by “(…) the certainty that a change in the way of possessing world power (Weltmachthaberschaft) was being prepared.” (ibid.)  Heidegger’s neologism Weltmachthaberschaft shows that for him world power is a kind of title of ownership, which passes, from one owner or ‘keeper’ to the next – like the registration of used cars.  The future owners (Inhaber) – the German Volk as trustee of Being - will though change the manner of this possession of power – as it will be a direct gift of Being to itself managed via its sole embodiment – the racially purified self-asserted German Volk.  Presumably once in German hand – world power will rest in itself like “the work”.

As no particle of the mass is a subject in its own right, but only as a quantitative/will-to-power following of the Führer – there is in the strict sense only one militant (subject) of the event – the Führer, who is the guarantee for the perpetuity of the mass, not as a collective subject – but as a count-as-one multiple – a multitude.
But is that enough?  The perpetuity of the mass is not identical with the longevity or perpetuity of the state.  Quite the opposite.  Both Heidegger and Carl Schmitt become quite entangled/mired in the difference between the two – ‘movement’ and ‘state’. 

Axiom:  There is a natural relation between Führer and Volk alias masses – but no natural relation between Führer and state – rather a non-relation or a mutual exclusion.

Peter Sloterdijk spoke of the “shameful contract” (naturally ‘Faustian’) between Führer and Volk in an episode of his television program “Philosophisches Quartett” (Youtube) in 2005 devoted to the German film Der Untergang (The Downfall) on the last days of Hitler in the Führerbunker.  None of the participants (the philosopher Rüdiger Safranski, the poet Durs Grünbein and the historian Jörg Friedrich) in their attempt to render intelligibility to the media figure of Hitler – mentioned the Nazi state with one word – let alone the ‘sovereign exception’.  Sloterdijk spoke of “Adolf Hitler – superstar”; Safranski insisted Hollywood could make the best film about the Nazi era – because it was all about one man and the German people who loved him and whom he later spurned, not about any “Systemzwänge” (system dictates), - and Hollywood is the world champion in “personalising”.  Friedrich seemed to agree – the essence of Hitler’s shamanic charm for the German people – was his promise of a psycho-historical miracle, the ‘cure’ – a promise magically compressed and ever present in the obligatory greeting formulae ‘Heil Hitler’ (Salvation Hitler) and ‘Sieg Heil’ (Victory Salvation).  Hitler, the people’s chosen charlatan, promised himself as the miracle cure able to turn a slave people (das Knechtvolk) who had been conquered and subjugated by foreign powers throughout its history, and again after losing the First World War – into the masters of the world.  Neither side could keep the promise.  Durs Grünbein thought now “the historians are finished (fertig) with Hitler”, which prompted Sloterdijk after some delay to say Sebastian Haffner’s Anmerkungen zu Hitler (Notes to Hitler) had given him at one time the hope one could finish with Hitler.  From such a program one can only conclude the Germans will never be finished with Hitler. 




   
The dictum “Führerwort hat Gesetzeskraft” (The Führer’s word has force of law) was a flimsy faux legalistic construction to disguise the non-relation between the Führer Hitler and a juridical state.  For both Heidegger and Schmitt – although with some subtle ontological differences – the political implies and presupposes the State – thus their ‘Hitlerian state’ is a non-being, a phantasm.
The Führer in the figure of Hitler had no successor.  A lack the Nazi state shared with the genre of all ‘sultanist’ states – as one can observe today in the Arab world, with the great difference that the German people/Volk did not engage in a mass uprising against their sultan.  On the contrary, the posthumous bonds of Führer-Eros have become sempiternal, passed on like a secret religion from one generation to the next, as constitutive for the contemporary German ‘oversoul’ as the ‘magic of the monarchy’ for the British national psyche – and yet the state if it is a state cannot end with the biological ending of one man.  This dilemma exercised Heidegger quite early – in fact the essential repeatability (iterability) of the ‘resolute choice’ appears already in paragraph 74 of Being and Time.  Repetition is almost the sine qua non of Dasein’s historicity as its expanded temporality.  The ‘ecstatic openness’ of Dasein to the future is grounded in its “inheritance” (Erbe) – in tradition (Überlieferung) or what is handed down and repetition (Wiederholung).  History is therefore weighted towards what has been (Gewesenheit).  Consequently in the Rectoral Address he will anticipate the beginning of the Nazi enterprise as already located in the future – as an ‘automatic’ tradition summoning the people to repeatedly commence towards their own and the ‘Greek’ past or beginning. 

[Commentary:  Is Foucault’s fascination with the anachronistic temporality of the Iranian movement – as something so apart from ‘Western’ modernity, itself not also a reflection of the pattern of the ‘great beginning’ Heidegger found in the ‘bursting forth’ of the Nazi movement?  Foucault went east and found a revival of something – a “political spirituality” and “an absolutely collective will” - ‘lost’ since the Renaissance in the west.  In the article “What are the Iranians dreaming about?” he attempts to interpret the phrase “Islamic government” in view of this eccentricity of time: ““A utopia,” some told me without any pejorative implication.  “An ideal,” most of them said to me.  At any rate, it is something very old and also very far into the future, a notion of coming back to what Islam was at the time of the Prophet, but also of advancing towards a luminous and distant point where it would be possible to renew fidelity rather than maintain obedience.  In pursuit of this ideal, the distrust of legalism seemed to me to be essential (…)” (Michel Foucault in Le Nouvel Observateur, October 16-22, 1978) Foucault was attracted to the Iranian uprising against the Shah in the way Genet was drawn to the Palestinian movement – but Genet, more true to his own law of perversity found the highest spirituality in betrayal – the revolt against fidelity.] 

Freedom for Heidegger is not to be taken singularly, but only as part of a dreadful quintet including death, guilt, conscience and finitude all housed or hosted by Sorge (Care) – it is the freedom to choose what has been.  Dasein though is not alone in his choice – or rather if Dasein has a fate or is fate – then most likely Dasein is in Being-With (Mitsein) and then all that happens to him is a happening-with and is elevated to a higher level of fate called “Geschick”.  Whatever happens to the community, to the people is designated as Geschick.  The fatefulness of Geschick though is opened (erschlossen) expressly by repetition, in its attachment (Verhaftung) to handed down traditions.  Presaging what he will say about the “Kampfgemeinschaft von Lehrer und Schüler” (the battle-community of teachers and pupils) at the conclusion of his Rectoral Address, Heidegger describes Dasein’s ‘freedom’ as “Treue zum Wiederholbaren” (fidelity to the repeatable) – sounding like a species-ancestor of Badiou’s “fidelity to the event”:  “Die eigentliche Wiederholung einer gewesenen Existenzmöglichkeit – daß das Dasein sich seinen Helden wählt – gründet existenzial in der vorlaufenden Entschlossenheit; denn in ihr wird allererst die Wahl gewählt, die für die kämpfende Nachfolge und Treue zum Wiederholbaren frei macht.” [“The proper repetition of a past existence possibility – that Dasein chooses its heroes – has its existential principle (reason, base) in the previous resoluteness; for it is in resoluteness that one first chooses the choice, which makes one free for the militant discipleship (succession, following) and the fidelity to the repeatable.”, (Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit, Tübingen, 1986 p. 385)]  “The fidelity to the repeatable” is one of the many instruments Heidegger uses in his ontological reconstitution of the Christian parousia.
Despite Heidegger’s fervent Hitlerism and advocacy of the Führerkult when he lectures to beginning students on the state and its people – the project for the longue durée – he hardly mentions the Führer – as if there were now an unspoken secret resolute choice awaiting - of either/or – Führer or State.  In a lecture of 1934 “The Present State and the Future Task of Philosophy” he sees the ontological difference immediately materialized/ontologized/reified in the relation of state as historical Being (Sein) and the people (Seiendes) as individual being(s): “Ein Staat ist nur, indem er wird, wird zum geschichtlichen Sein des Seienden, das Volk heißt.” (“A state is only while it becomes, becomes the historical being of individual being, which is called the people.”, cited in Faye, ibid., p. 85)

Mussolini was a witness and archive of the future type.  The Nazi/fascist university is implicitly connected to what Lacoue-Labarthe calls the humanism of Nazism.  The human as defined by the Nazi/fascist university – the type of the human.  Is this humanism also identical with the ‘ideology of the subject as another name for fascism/fascist’ – as proposed in “The Nazi Myth”?
“It would be (…) necessary to rigorously demonstrate how the Total State is to be conceived as the Subject-State (whether it be a nation or humanity, whether it be a class, a race, or a party, this subject is or wills itself to be an absolute subject), such that in the last instance it is in modern philosophy, in the fully realized metaphysics of the Subject, that ideology finds its real guarantee: that is to say, in the thought of being (and/or of becoming, of history) defined as a subjectivity present to itself, as the support, the source, and the finality of representation, certitude, and will. (…) The ideology of the subject (which, perhaps, is no more than a pleonasm) is fascism, the definition holding, of course, for today.”
(Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe and Jean-Luc Nancy, “The Nazi Myth” Critical Inquiry 16, University of Chicago Press, Winter 1990, pp. 293- 294)  If then, ideology requires modern philosophy as its “real guarantee” of the thought of being and/or becoming of history, defined as subjectivity etc and this ideology is fascism – then one is led to conclude that for these authors – modern philosophy is also fascism.

Self-assertion as a mode of augmenting the power of the state is the fascist/Nazi novum in the technologies or techniques of governance.  This self-assertion could be seen as the ‘humanism’ of Nazism.  The self-asserted Volks-singularity is its ‘ideology of the subject’. As Adorno writes – “Dasein is merely a German and ashamed version of the subject.” (Theodor W. Adorno, Negative Dialektik, ibid., p. 114)

But Heidegger cautions his reader that “Dasein istje meines; dies bedeutet weder: durch mich gesetzt, noch: auf ein vereinzeltes Ich abgesondert.” (“Dasein is “respectively mine”; this means neither: posited by me, nor: isolated in a singularized I.”, Einführung in die Metaphysik, ibid., p. 22)  What does that mean?  Mine but not I?  But a subject - at least in a modified or reduced sense?  If Dasein in Sein und Zeit is a “deutsche und verschämte Variante von Subjekt” (Adorno, ibid.) – Dasein in Einführung in die Metaphysik presupposes a racial community of Mitsein (being-with) from which it projects its subjecthood.  This is the succession of Heidegger’s thought of being from Dasein to the racially determined self-assertion.  Racial thought for Heidegger is the fulfilment of metaphysics or (what is the same) the metaphysics of the subject.  If Dasein was ultimately only viable within the ‘historicity’ of a people (the German people, Volk) the figure of self-assertion presupposes the experience of being as race.  Race is the crucial nexus in Heidegger’s thought between being and “the political”.  A self-asserting Dasein within the limits of race – is more fundamental and yet in turn presupposes the political.  Race, Dasein, self-assertion and the political can barely be disentangled.  This is also where Heidegger criticizes Carl Schmitt’s “concept of the political”. 

[Commentary: Heidegger’s self-assertion is affirmative and is the original determination of the political prior to the friend/enemy distinction of Schmittian provenance.  The friend/enemy dichotomy, a negative distinction according to Heidegger, presupposes self-assertion and is only an essential consequence of the political. (Heidegger, “Hegel, On the State”, winter 1934-1935, cited in Faye, ibid., pp. 240-241) But Heidegger’s insistence on the sequence within this row sounds more like quibbling about nuance than any fundamental sort of correction.]


Hence sovereignty does not capture the political ‘essence’ of the Nazi entity – the distinction between governed and governor is dissolved/sublated in self-assertion.  In the terms of Heidegger’s Rectoral Address – this delicate balance between governors and governed is precisely defined by a highly regulated/ritualized ‘polemos’ (battle).  The university is paradigmatic of the state – master and pupil confront one another as governor and governed, leader and follower.



 
It is the “scene of “hegemony”” (Lacoue-Labarthe) in the Rectoral speech.  Hegemony is the result of the battle of their two ‘wills to essence’ – so that hegemony miraculously becomes through a progression of self-examinations – “self-governance”.  The battle though is self-contained, the outcome foregone.  There is really only one side to this ‘agon’ – it is the familiar static block (stasis) of Mitsein (being-with or the absence of any ‘alterity’) transformed in keeping with the jargon of the times into a “Kampfgemeinschaft der Lehrer und Schüler” (battle-community of teachers and pupils).  Although leading and following is an opposition of essence (Wesensgegensatz) – ‘leading granting following its strength, and following having its resistance within’ – all of this remains steadfastly incestuously bracketed in the circularity of Nazi state and German people. 
It is the calculated battle of the people who wills itself, who decides with – and that has already been decided elsewhere.  “We do will ourselves.  For the young strength of the people, which already reaches beyond us, has by now decided the matter.” (Martin Heidegger, The Self-Assertion of the German University and The Rectorate 1933/1934: Facts and Thoughts, Review of Metaphysics, 38:3 (1985:Mar.) p. 480)  For the “knowing battle of those who question” (ibid.) conjures up a field of imminent danger threatening ‘the battle community’ from which they must rescue themselves - but risk and danger hold themselves in the balance.  The ‘battle’ is an effect of a ‘decision’ of the power, which lies already beyond the ‘accomplices’ of science (Mitwissenschaft) – who will them to will themselves.  The ‘revolt against that which is’ is identical with ‘what is’.  


How disturbing it must have been though for Heidegger that the longevity and repeatability (iterability) of the Nazi state or historical Being (geschichtliches Sein) dangled on the fragile life thread of one ephemeral ‘hero’ even if he were the people’s, individual being’s (Seiendes) resolute choice.     
 
Besides the biopolitics of sovereign power and ‘life’, there is another equally crucial biopolitical void within sovereign power itself, mostly overlooked by philosophers of biopolitics, though far more real than the fictive relation between sovereign and subject biologicals.  The historical dilemma of “the two bodies of the king” encompasses the abyssal distance between ‘bare life and sovereign power’ in the figure of the sovereign himself.  Just as the mortality of dynasties (Ibn Khaldun), dynastic mating and inbreeding (the Habsburg chin) reflect how this insurmountable difference of the ‘two bodies’ is handed down from one generation to the next.  The dynasty (also state, party) is simply the trans-generational ‘two bodies of the king’ over a finite period of time.  The ‘two bodies of the king’ are an aporia within sovereignty.
Hitler invaded the pattern of the ‘two bodies of the king’: – the destructible negligible vehicle – the physical king – who must be sacrificed in each generation on the eternal altar of the monarchy (the striking dramatic exposition thereof is Shakespeare’s Richard the Second): to prove that le roi se meurt jamais (the king never dies).  The biological-political body of Hitler is not just the shared location of zoē and bios (Agamben) but also the repository of mass polymorphous sexual desire – known as Führer Eros or “Liebe zum Führer” (love of the Führer).  In the “austere monarchy of sex” – his rule is grounded in the sexual dispositif, the mystical authority of sex, that Foucault discovers as the premise and (‘archaic’, original?) rhythm of biopolitics (see Michel Foucault, La volonté de savoir).  In that sense Hitler does not rule, he is a body-mask, a contingent historical regent of ‘king sex’.  His form of rule exemplifies a major axiom of Anti-Oedipus: “(…) desire is part of the infrastructure.” (Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, Anti-Oedipus Capitalism and Schizophrenia, Minneapolis, 1983, p. 104)


[Commentary:  Is Nazism’s form of power – unburdened of the juridical scaffolding – positioned more immediately in the field of sexual desire than the conventional juridical form of sovereignty?  Does Nazism’s non-juridical, non-state power enter with its commands and biological dictates more directly into a relation to sex and desire than law based models of sovereignty?
More directly sexual in other words?  Is that what Foucault means by biopolitics?  If that were the case though – given his claim that biopolitics has become the totality of politics, then the libidinal economy would, in his eyes, surpass even the money and capital economy – that other vast and ubiquitous form of non-juridical power situated nowhere and everywhere – certainly not in something as insignificant as a state.  One can see today during the present economic crisis (in the sense of eternal presence and return) how the power of money and capital is shaking one state sovereignty and government after the other.]  
 

The measure of the longevity of the Third Reich though was Hitler’s political-sexual body - the time remaining to his own mortal shell.  Thus the haste and speed with which events evolved in Nazi Germany.  Hitler had to have his war by a certain age, the tempo of the Third Reich, its occupations, invasions, the extermination of the Jewish people, were synchronized with his physiological rhythms.  The body of state (the Reich) became the ephemeral negligible vehicle of Hitler’s immortality-undertaking to impose (write) his biological “lifetime” on “worldtime” (see Hans Blumenberg, Lebenszeit und Weltzeit, Frankfurt, 1986).  For that certain period of twelve years give or take - the flesh and sex of Hitler became the biological clock of the world.  If he and his sexual vassals, the Nazi Volk, had no time, the world should have no time either.